#cover m-b-murray-bookchin-the-philosophy-of-social-ecolo-2.png
#pubdate 2019-07-24
#title The Philosophy of Social Ecology
#subtitle Essays on Dialectical Naturalism
#LISTtitle Philosophy of Social Ecology
#author Murray Bookchin
#SORTtopics philosophy, social ecology, dialectics, green anarchism, nature
#date 1996
#source [[https://libcom.org/library/philosophy-social-ecology-essays-dialectical-naturalism][libcom]] and [[https://archive.org/stream/PhilosophyOfSocialEcology/Philosophy%20of%20Social%20Ecology_djvu.txt][Internet Archive]]
#lang en
#notes Second Edition.
** Dedication | ~~
*For Janet Biehl,*
*dearest of companions and closest of colleagues*
** Preface to the Second Edition
This edition of *The Philosophy of Social Ecology* has been so radically revised and corrected that in many respects it is a new
book. I have retained in most of their essentials the essays that
appeared in the first edition, but I have significantly altered
many of my original formulations. I have also added a new
essay, “History, Civilization, and Progress” written early in
1994, which critically examines in general terms the social and
ethical relativism so much in vogue today.
Most of the essays in this book were written as polemics,
directed against various tendencies that surfaced in the American
ecology movement in the 1980s. “Toward a Philosophy of Nature,”
published in Michael Tobin’s misnamed collection, *Deep Ecology*, in
1985 but written three years earlier for the journal *Telos*, was
directed against the then-current enthusiasm for turning systems
theory into ecological philosophy. “Freedom and Necessity in Nature,” published in the Canadian journal *Alternatives* in 1986, challenged the neo-Darwinian view of the natural world fostered by a
cluster of very conventional ecologists and initiated my critique of
“biocentrism.” “Thinking Ecologically,” initially published in 1987
in another Canadian journal. *Our Generation*, was written to
criticize the New Age “paradigm” that was then being inflicted on
the ecology movement, as well as certain leaders of Earth First!,
who were then advancing a crudely misanthropic message from
their stronghold in the American Sunbelt. Appearing here in the
order in which they were written (except for the introduction),
they are thus set in very distinct time frames, with emphases appropriate to issues that have emerged over the past fourteen years.
I wish to thank all previous publishers of these essays for their
permission to republish them, both in the original and in this
revised edition.
Although times have changed since these essays first appeared, the problems they tried to address are still with us. Gregory
Bateson’s views no longer enjoy the preeminence that they did in
the 1980s, for example, but his subjectivism and many of his arguments played a major role in forming the innerworldly, relativistic,
and personalistic Zeitgeist of present New Age ideologues, while
systems theory approaches still surface in many current theoretical works on ecology. Fritjof Capra is still fostering his eclectic
medley of science and mysticism, of Prigoginian systems theory
and “California cosmology.” “Biocentrism,” antihumanism, deep
ecology, and neo-Malthusianism have become even more popular
than they were when I wrote “Thinking Ecologically.” New views
have melded with older ones: today, it is philosophical relativism
and postmodernism that are percolating through the ecology
movement; hence the new closing essay, “History, Civilization, and
Progress.” In revising all the essays, I have tried to generaiize the
views expressed in the original versions to make them as relevant
as possible to present-day discussion. Let me add that without the
assistance and editorial insights of Janet Biehl, to whom this book
is dedicated, these revisions would have bee n difficult to make. I
would also like to express my thanks to Nathalie Klym at Black
Rose Books for her valuable work in producing this book.
Two other changes in the present edition should be
singled out. First, I have excised favorable references to the
Frankfurt School and Theodor Adorno. like Leszek Kolakowski, I
have come to regard much of Adorno’s work as intellectually irresponsible, wayward, and poorly theorized, despite the brilliance of his style (at times) and his often insightful epigrams. This is not to reject his defense of speculative reason against positivism — which was what initially attracted me to his work
and to the Frankfurt School — even as h is writings exude enormous pessimism about reason and its destiny.
Second, I have removed my favorable allusions to ideas
that have since become central to ecofeminism. The exciting challenge that radical feminism posed in the early 1970s was its
universal condemnation of hierarchy as such, which appealed to
me since I myself had made such a condemnation more than a
decade earlier. Even in the late 1970s, when ecofeminism
emerged, claims of the “innate” superiority of females over m ales
and of women’s superior emotional and cognitive abilities, and
opposition to “logocentrism,” were not yet prominent. Only later
was ecofeminism reduced to the antirational and crudely visceral
level of a Starhawk, where invocations of magic, goddess worship,
and witchcraft become “feminist” ways of eluding reality. Too
many ecofeminists, albeit not all, now tend to privilege women
over men cognitively and morally, while the original universalist
and egalitarian approach of the feminist movement has withered
significantly.
Whether the reader agrees with all my views or not, these
essays, I believe, are required reading for anyone who wishes to
understand social ecology. They seek, more suggestively than exhaustively, to establish its philosophical foundations and modes of thought. (Let me insist that they are the works of neither a “Hegelian,” a “neo-Hegelian,” nor a “post-Hegelian,” to use current academic jargon, but rather of a *dialectician* upon whom Hegel exercised a considerable influence.) A rounded understanding of social ecology as I have formulated it, however, also requires a reading of at least two of my other books, *Remaking Society* and *Urbanization Without Cities*, which explore social ecology’s historical and political aspects.
Recent developments in quasi-leftist social thinking have
obliged me to significantly alter the way I conceive *nature*, *society*,
and *reason*, as well as *history*, *civilization*, and *progress*, as the
reader will find in the closing essay. All these words have a multiplicity of meanings, but the meanings that are most pervasive
today are not the ones that I intend when I use these words.
Nowadays, for example, the ecology movement most often
regards *nature* either as a “social construction” or a “wilderness”
of one sort or another, while others see *society* as *any* aggregation
of life-forms, including flocks of birds and herds of deer. Both
within and without the ecology movement, *reason* is regarded as a
mental skill, *history* as a mere succession of events, *civilization* as a
Eurocentric prejudice, and progress as a myth. Years of give-and-take with both supporters and opponents of my views have
obliged me to slowly but consciously give these words a more
specific philosophical meaning than they have in conventional
discourse. Some of these changes are discussed in the new introduction to the Black Rose edition of *The Ecology of Freedom*; others
require elucidation here.
As I explain in the introduction to this book. *Nature* properly encompasses everything around us, from the organic beings
that we normally designate as “natural” to the lifeless moon that
appears on relatively cloudless nights — that is, the totality of
Being. However, if we are to use the word *Nature* in any more
specific sense, we should use an adjective before it to describe
what *aspect* of “nature” we are talking about — something that I
often did not do in these essays, owing to the time period in
which they were written. The reader who encounters the word
*nature* herein, unmodified by any adjective, should now take it to
refer to my notion of “first nature,” or the cumulative evolution of
the natural world, especially the organic world. This first nature
exists in both continuity *and* discontinuity with “second nature,”
or the evolution of society. As I discuss in some detail in “Thinking Ecologically,” second nature develops both in continuity with
first nature and as its antithesis, until the two are subbed into
“free nature” or “Nature” rendered self-conscious in a rational
and ecological society.
*Society*, in turn, is more than mere consociation or
community. It is *institutionalized* community, structured a ro und
mutable organizational forms that may range from totalitarian
despotism to libertarian municipalism. As such, society is specific
to human beings; indeed, an expression like “social insects” is,
from my standpoint, nonsensical and oxymoronic, conflating a
fixed, genetically programmed aggregation of animals with the
developmentally structured consociation of humans. As for *reason*
and *rationality*, when I use these terms without any qualifying adjective, I mean *dialectical reason*, a secular dialectical *logos*, as contrasted with *instrumental* or *conventional reason*, an ordinary
mental skill. *History*, as I argue in the final essay, is the cultural
and social unfolding of reason, not simply a succession of events
over time, for which I reserve the word *Chronicles*. *Civilization* is
the actualization in varying degrees of historical unfolding, while
*Progress* is, more loosely, the self-directive activity of History and
Civilization toward increasing rationality, freedom, and self-consciousness in relationships between human and human, and in the relationship of humanity to the natural world.
Let me state as clearly and firmly as possible that I do not
regard History and Progress as unilinear, inevitable, teleological,
or in any sense predetermined. The power of speculative reason to
logically project beyond the given into what is yet to come *if*
humanity acts rationally — a power that is one of our highest
*human* attributes — does not mean that what rationally “should be”
will indeed *necessarily* “be.” To constitute the all-important standard by which we may judge the rationality of a society is a firmly
held function of dialectical reason. We would lose ourselves in a
quagmire of solipsistic relativism if we were to abdicate the power
of reason to “judge” History, Civilization, and Progress. Even the
most dyed-in-the-wool antirationalists and relativists exercise this
power, irrespective of their convictions against doing so. As any
thinking person would agree, people do indeed imagine the world
as it *might* be, in contrast to what it *is* in reality, even in their
daydreams. They do have the wildest fantasies about their culture
and its environment. And they do hold the most seemingly unrealistic constellations of images and “patterns of culture” about
basic aspects of their experience. None of this do I deny — quite the
contrary, humanity’s continual *struggle* with its imagination lies at
the very heart of the tensions within early society, which in turn
has historically led to varying degrees of rational self-understanding as well as frightening, often atavistic regressions.
Given these observations, it would be simplistic and one-sided to ignore the moral and cultural paradoxes embedded in social development. Humanity did not emerge *ab novo*, without roots
in animal evolution. The human being has been and still is an
animal with emotional states that are animalistic, like “fight and
flight” reactions and tormentingly basic fears. But humans are also
animals of a very special kind: we are highly intelligent by comparison with other species — indeed, qualitatively so — and as
such, we have the ability not only to adapt to our environments but
intentionally to alter them significantly. In short, we can do m ore
than adapt; we can *innovate*, although we do not always innovate
willingly if we can survive in a given environment without doing so.
Our intelligence is also highly problematic. It makes not
only for innovation but for foresight, fantasy, imagination,
creativity — and cruelty. Indeed, much personal and social irrationality *stems* from the intentionally, will, self-assertiveness, and
fantasies of our animality informed by our intelligence. As Marx
suggested, we still live in prehistory and have yet to find our way
toward a self-conscious, humane, cooperative, and empathetic social life. With our animalistic as well as human attributes, we
evolve in an ever-changing world and face stark problems of survival and well-being. Apart from those people who inhabit places
with benign physiographic conditions, we are subject to material
insecurity, contesting wills, challenges to our sense of self and
self-regard, fears of disease, diminishing physical powers with
age, frightening dreams, and so forth. We address these abiding
problems with relatively developed minds that are still encased, as it
were, in extremely potent animal attributes.
History is the painful movement of human beings in extricating themselves from animal existence, of the emergence of
tensions from a combination of nonhuman and human attributes,
and of progressively advancing toward a more universally
human state of affairs, however irregular or unsteady this advance may be. The problems that humans retain from early
society continue to exist in one way or another to this day, and
their resolution in part or whole is one of the meaningful goals of
History, even as new problems arise over the course of time. Nor
is there any certainty that these problems will be resolved. A descent into barbarism — a problematic that Marxists were raising
during the grimmest years of World War II — is just as possible as
the attainment of a rational society.
But to deny, because of such starkly conflicting alternatives in social development, that there are rational criteria by
which we may judge that Progress is myopic, or even that
Progress has occurred, is self-deceptive. It is all too easy to rebuke
History if one minimizes the genuine advances that have been
made in culture, social relations, and technics. All doubts about
History, Civilization, and Progress aside, it is undeniable that we
have divested ourselves of many of the kinship ties that
parochialized us into tribal groups, and that we have accepted —
albeit with many qualifications — our status as a *human* species
rather than as a *folk*. We have created cities that are open to
strangers, we have advanced technology to the point that a sufficiency in the means of life could be available to all in a rational
society, and we have increased our knowledge of the natural
world to almost sublime proportions. Not only do we kill each
other with terrifying brutality, given our combination of animality with intelligence, but we help each other on a massive
scale with extraordinary sensitivity.
Here, I believe, we are obliged to make a serious decision
about how we look at the past. Either we will relativize History by
emphasizing the power of the irrational over human behavior and
the endless differences that distinguish cultures from one
another; or we will emphasize the remarkable coherence of
various cultures and generalize from their similarities, even as we
appreciate their differences. Choosing the first alternative would
ultimately diminish social development to a disconnected archipelago of wholly unique cultures whose only Coherence is
psychosocial and internal; while the second alternative would
allow for a dialectically rational understanding of History and a
ground for ethics. If our animalistic *capacity* for irrational behavior gains priority over our humanistic *potentiality* to act rationally, and if social development becomes only an ensemble of
*Chronicles* (if even that) rather than a *History* of maturation, there
is no basis for striving to achieve a rational society.
What, then, of those social failures, aberrations, horrors,
and breakdowns that belie humanity’s unilinear progress toward
Civilization and freedom?[1] Without in any way *understating* this
problematic, we must be wary of *overstating* it by dissolving social
development in psychosocial interpretations, thereby minimizing
the very reality of social maturation as such. There has been a historical social development, all its many setbacks notwithstanding,
setbacks that can in part be attributed to elites of agonistic men
whose power gave them the scope to play out their destructive
fantasies, impulses, and designs on a large social stage. In their
activities they have “gone too far” so to speak, demonically pushing cultures beyond the rational framework of their historical
time. Such distortions become especially problematical during
times of transition, when established social formations are being
negated and new ones are emerging with uncertainty and ambiguity. This overextension of the “negative” (to use Hegel’s term)
occurred at numerous times and in numerous places, when “antitheses” became ends in themselves and did not develop as a rational or progressive transcendence. Neither tribal, feudal,
autocratic, republican, nor even classical democratic political systems have been historically immune to this phenomenon.
And yet it would be a gross simplification of social
development to ahistorically dichotomize the hierarchical, class,
and even state formations of the past, on the one hand, and the
torturous efforts of humanity to advance toward freedom, on the
other. Paradoxically, in its emergence out of barbarism—indeed,
out of simple animality — humanity may have had to depend
upon priests, chieftains, and perhaps state-like formations to
overcome parochialism, lack of individuality, kinship bonds,
gerontocracies, and patriarchies, to cite some key social features
of tribal and even civilized cultures. “Evils” these are, to be sure,
but, if we are to believe Michael Bakunin, “socially necessary
evils,” a phrase with which he historically characterized the state
and that Peter Kropotkin echoed in his famous *Encyclopaedia Britannica* article, “Anarchism” The groundwork for making a
civilizatory process possible — notably the emergence of cities, territorial forms of consociation, writing, an expanding moral sensibility, a rational and incipiently secular outlook on the world,
technological advances that led to agriculture, metallurgy, and
relatively sophisticated crafts — all may have required what we
would regard today as unacceptable institutions of social control
but that at an earlier time may have been important in launching
a rational social development.
In any case, to ahistorically counter pose “virtue” to
“evil” without *any* historical qualifications and mediations can
be very naive. In much earlier historical eras, “good” and
“evil” had not even acquired the definitions they have today,
after thousands of years of human social development. The state’s
invasion of patriarchal authority; its substitution of a relatively
rational system of law for the patriarch’s arbitrary and absolute authority over all other members of a family or clan;
and the abrogation of blood vengeance as a way of resolving
conflicts — all, to cite some significant advances, played a role
that was relatively liberatory in its historical context, give n a
general framework of domination in early hierarchical
societies. Patriarchs, for example, would have seen the state’s
function in this respect as “evil.”
Like the historical replacement of kinship ties with civic
ties, barter with markets, agrarian isolation with cities, particularism with growing universalism, and superstition with
secularism, there were certain forms of socially regulative institutions that, while oppressive in modern eyes, opened possibilities
for liberatory developments that otherwise might never have
emerged. But although the very real barbarism of past and
present remains an “evil,” as Bakunin observed, it was not a historical “necessity” in any sense akin to Bakunin’s, for we can
never know what rational alternatives may have existed at any
time. At no time can we surrender to the “inevitability” of
domination in certainty that latent liberatory possibilities do not
exist.
In no sense, then, should my remarks be seen as an “excuse” for barbaric behavior, past or present. Rather, I intend them
in great part to be the premise for trying to *understand* how it is
that the irrational dimensions of the past, with their many barbarities, never completely stifled the rational development of
humanity and yet may have even interacted with it at times to
yield social advances within a broadly evil framework. It behooves
us to study the historical and social *interactions* between the legacy
of freedom and the legacy of domination, in degree as well as in
kind, not to simplify them or even brush them aside with
psychosocial categories or ahistorically enumerate them on a social ledger of debits and credits. If we are to think in a graded and
nuanced manner, with a modicum of intellectual responsibility, about
the past and present, we are obliged to explore the social conditions in which — offensive as it may seem to “politically correct”
modern minds — certain forms of domination paradoxically
provided the stimulus for increasing freedom, culturally if not institutionally.
Do we have no other ground than our personal preferences
for dealing with the social issues of the past and present? Attitudes, wishes, desires, and imagined ways of life are deeply
rooted in existing social conditions — not even our most liberating
“preferences” have solely personal origins. Today they reflect possibilities and hopes that were not available to the radical culture of
only a few generations ago. The cry to “demand the impossible,”
which surfaced among French students in May-June 1968, rested
massively on the extraordinary *possibilities* that advances in technology and material life had opened up, not simply on alienation — which, in fact, these very advances significantly generated.
The essays in this book critique the common view that —
owing to the “impossibility” of formulating an objective criterion
for determining what is rational or irrational, real or imaginary,
true or false, good or evil, self-determining or authoritarian — our
attitude that freedom is desirable and tyranny hateful must have
only a contingent subjective basis. When this attitude is formed *in*
*abstracto*, without any roots in historical development or material
preconditions, it remains theoretically unjustified and a mere matter of opinion. Unfortunately, this is an indulgence we can ill afford. The condition of the world is far too desperate and chaotic
for us, often from the fastness of the academy, to advance a moral,
social, and cultural incoherence that rests primarily on attitudes,
tastes, and matters of opinion that themselves beg for rational explanation.
— March 15,1994
[1] The notion of a unilinear social development, like the one Friedrich
Engels presented in *Anti-Duhring*, had already fallen into considerable
disrepute among serious Marxists in the first half of this century, as I
myself recall. One of the most troubling problems with this notion, I
should note, was the “transition” from feudalism to capitalism. For my
own part, I clearly challenged the idea that capitalism was the “inevitable” successor of feudalism in *Urbanization Without Cities*. There I
argued that capitalism, from the fourteenth century until well into the
eighteenth and early nineteenth, was merely part of “a mixed economy
which was neither feudal, capitalist, nor structured around simple
commodity production. Rather, it contained and combined elements of
all three forms.” Economically as well as culturally, an open situation,
so to speak, existed that could quite conceivably have led to more
benign social advances and avoided the horrors that capitalism
brought into the world. *See Urbanization Without Cities* (originally published as *The Rise of Urbanization and the Decline of Citizenship* by Sierra
Club Books in 1987; published in Canada by Montreal: Black Rose
Books, 1992), pp. 198–201. In this book I consistently emphasize the significance of libertarian municipalist confederations in opposition to
the state — historically as well as contemporaneously.
** Introduction:
A Philosophical Naturalism
What is nature? What is humanity’s place in nature? And what is
the relationship of society to the natural world?
In an era of ecological breakdown, answering these questions has become of momentous importance for our everyday
lives and for the future that we and other life-forms face. They
are not abstract philosophical questions that should be relegated
to a remote, airy world of metaphysical speculation. Nor can we
answer them in an offhand way, with poetic metaphors or unthinking, visceral reactions. The definitions and ethical standards
with which we respond to them may ultimately decide whether
human society will creatively foster natural evolution, or whether
we will render the planet uninhabitable for all complex life-forms, including ourselves.
At first glance, everybody “knows” what nature is. It is that
which is all around us — trees, animals, rocks, and the like. It is
that which “humanity” is coating with petroleum or destroying.
But such prima facie definitions fall apart when we examine them
with some care. If nature is indeed what is all around us, we may
reasonably ask, then, is a carefully manicured suburban lawn not
nature? Is the split-level house it surrounds not nature? Are its
furnishings not natural?
Today, this sort of question is likely to elicit a heated avowal
that only wild, primordial,” or even nonhuman nature is
authentically natural. Other people, no less thoughtful, will reply
that nature is basically matter, or the materialized stuff of the
universe in all its forms — what philosophers sweepingly rail Being.
The fact is that wide philosophical differences have existed for centuries in the West over the very definition of toe word nature. These
differences remain unresolved to this day, even as nature is making
headlines in environmental issues that are of enormous importance for the future of nearly all life-forms.
Defining nature *becomes* an even more complex task when
we include the human species as part of it. Is human society with
its ensemble of technologies and artifacts — not to speak of such
ineffable features as its conflicting social interests and institutions — any less part of nature than nonhuman animals? And if
human beings are part of nature, are they merely one life-form
among many others, or are they unique in ways that place major
responsibilities on them with respect to the rest of the world of
life, responsibilities that no other species shares or is even capable
of sharing?
Whatever *nature* may mean, we must determine in what
way humanity “fits” into it And we must confront the complex
and challenging question of the relationship of society — more
specifically, the different social forms that appeared in the past,
that exist today, and that may appear in the future — to nature.
Unless we answer these questions with reasonable clarity — or at
least fully discuss them — we will lack any ethical direction in
dealing with our environmental problems. Unless we know what
nature is and what humanity’s and society’s place in it is, we will
be left with vague intuitions and visceral sentiments that neither
cohere into clear views nor provide a guide for effective action.
----
It is easy to try to escape answering these troubling questions by
impatiently rejecting them, responding with pure emotion, or
simply denigrating any effort to reason out a coherent reply —
indeed, by attacking *reason* itself as “meddlesome” (to use William Blake’s term). Today, even sensitive people in growing
numbers feel betrayed by the centuries-long glorification of
reason, with its icy claims to efficiency, objectivity, and freedom
from ethical constraint — or the form of reason that has
nourished particularly destructive technologies like nucleonics
and weaponry. This negative popular reaction is understandable. But swerving away from a specific form of reason
that is largely instrumental and coldly analytical creates
problems that are no less disturbing than those questions from
which we are seeking to escape.
In our aversion to an insensitive and unfeeling form of
reason, we may easily opt for a cloudy intuitionism and
mysticism as an alternative. Unlike instrumental and analytical
reason, after all, a surrender to emotion and mythic beliefs yields
cooperative feelings of “interconnectedness” with the natural
world and perhaps even a caring attitude toward it But precisely
because intuition and “mystical beliefs” are so cloudy and arbitrary — which is to say, so unreasoned — they may also “connect” us with things we really shouldn’t be connected with at all — namely, racism, sexism, and an abject subservience to charismatic
leaders.
Indeed, following this intuitional alternative could
potentially render our ecological outlook very dangerous. Vital as
the idea of “interconnectedness” may be to our views, it has historically often been the basis of myths and supernatural beliefs
that became means for social control and political manipulation.
The first half of the twentieth century is in great part the story of
brutal movements like National Socialism that fed on a popular
antirationalism and anti-intellectualism, and a personal sense of
alienation, among other things. This movement mobilized and
homogenized millions of people with an antisocial, perverted
“ecologistic” ideology based on intuition, with an “interconnectedness” of earth, folk, and “blood and soil” that was militaristic
and murderous rather than freely communitarian. Insulated from
the challenge of rational critique by its anti-intellectualism and
mythic nationalism, the National Socialist movement eventually
turned much of Europe into a cemetery. Yet ideologically, this fascist totalitarianism had gained sustenance from the intuitional and
mystical credo of the Romantic movement of the century before —
something no one could have foreseen at the time.
Feeling, sentiment, and a moral outlook we surely need if
instrumental and analytical reason are not to divest us of our
*passion* for truth. But myths, mind-numbing rituals, and charismatic
personalities can also rob us of the critical faculties that thought
provides. Recently, a Green organization in Canada flippantly
proclaimed that it seeks “cooperation” as part of its “new
paradigm” rather than “confrontation” which it considers part of
the rejected “old paradigm.” In a more radical era, confrontation
was the stated purpose of radical movements! The mythic and
uncritical aspect of “interconnectedness” that rejects confrontation seems to have reduced this Canadian Green organization to
the level of outright accommodation with the status quo. Here,
the need not only to confront the evils of our time but to Uncompromisingly oppose them has disappeared into a New Age quagmire of unthinking “good vibes.” The “loving” path of compromises along which such “good vibes” leads us can easily ending
sheer opportunism.
If our contemporary revolt against reason rests on the misguided belief that the only alternative to our present reality is
mysticism, it also rests on the equally misguided belief that only
one kind of reason exists. In reacting against instrumental and
analytical forms of reason, which are usually identified with
reason as such, we may well overlook other “forms of reason” that are
organic and yet retain critical qualities; that are developmental
and yet retain analytical insights; that are ethical and yet retain
contact with reality. The “value-free” rationalism that we normally identify with the physical sciences and technology is in fact not
the only form of reason that Western philosophy has developed
over the centuries — I refer specifically to the great tradition of
dialectical reason that originated in Greece some twenty~five centuries ago and reached its high point, but by no means its completion, in the logical works of Hegel.
What dialectical thinkers from Heraclitus onward have
had in common, in varying degrees, is a view of reality; as
developmental — of *Being* as an ever-unfolding *Becoming*. Ever
since Plato created a dualism between a supranatural world of
ideal forms and a transient world of imperfect sensible copies, the
perplexing question of identity amid change and change amid
identity has haunted Western philosophy,. Instrumental and
analytical forms of reason — what I will here generically call *conventional reason*[2] — rest on a fundamental principle, the famous
“principle of identity,” or A *equals* A, which means that any given
phenomenon can be only itself and cannot be other than what it
is, or what we immediately perceive it to be, at a given moment in
time. Without this principle, logical consistency in conventional
reason would be impossible.
Conventional reason is based on an analysis of phenomena as precisely defined, and whose truth depends upon their
internal consistency and practicality. It focuses on a thing or
phenomenon as fixed, with clear-cut boundaries that are immutable for analytical purposes. We know an entity, in this
widely accepted notion of reason, when we can analyze it into
its irreducible components and determine how they work as a
functioning whole so that knowledge of the entity will have
operational applicability. When the boundaries that “define” a
developing thing change — as, for instance, when sand becomes
soil — then conventional reason treats sand as sand and soil as
soil, much as if they were independent of each other. The *zone of interest* in this kind of rationality is a thing or phenomenon’s
fixity, its independence, and its basically mechanical interaction
with similar or dissimilar things and phenomena. The causality
that conventional reason describes, moreover, is a matter of
kinetics: one billiard ball strikes another and causes them both
to move from one position to another — that is to say, by means
of — efficient cause. The two billiard balls are not altered by the
blow but are merely repositioned on the billiard table.
But conventional reason cannot address the problem of
change at all. It views a mammal, for example, as a creature
marked by a highly fixed set of traits that distinguish it from
everything that is not mammalian. To “know” a mammal is to
explore its structure, literally to analyze it by dismembering it, to
reduce it to its components, to identify its organs and their functions, and to ascertain the way they operate together to assure
the mammal’s survival and reproduction. Similarly, conventional reason, views a human being in terms of particular stages of
the life-cycle: a person is an infant at one time, a child at
another, an adolescent at still another, a youth and finally an
adult. When we analyze an infant by means of conventional
reason, we do not explore what it is *becoming* in the process of
developing into an adult Doubtless, when developmental
psychologists and anatomists study an individual life-cycle, few of
them — however conventional their rationality may be — ignore the
fact that every infant is in the process of becoming an adult and
that the two stages in the life-cycle are in various ways related to
each other. But the principle of A *equals* A remains a basic premise.
Its logical framework is the authority of consistency, and deductions almost mechanically follow from premises. Conventional
reason thus serves the practical function of describing a given
entity’s identity and telling us how that entity is organized to be itself. But it cannot systematically explore processes of becoming, or
how a living entity is patterned as a *potentiality* to phase from one
stage of its development into another.
Dialectical reason, unlike conventional reason, acknowledges the developmental nature of reality by asserting in one
fashion or another that *A equals not only A but also not-A*. The
dialectical thinker who examines the human life-cycle sees an
infant as a self-maintaining human identity while simultaneously developing into a child, from a child into an adolescent, from
an adolescent into a youth, and from a youth into an adult.
Dialectical reason grasps not only how an entity is organized at
a particular moment but how it is organized to go beyond that
level of development and *become* other than what it is, even as it
retains its identity. The contradictory nature of identity — notably,
that *A equals both A and not-A* — is an intrinsic feature of identity
itself. The unity of opposites is, in fact, a unity qua the emerging
“other” what Hegel called “the identity of identity and nonidentity”
The thinking of conventional reason today is exemplified —
and disastrously reinforced — by the “true or false” questions that
make up most standardized tests. One must darken a box to indicate that a statement is either “true” or “false” — and do so quickly,
with minimal reflection. These tests, so commonplace today, allow
for no nuanced thought or awareness of transitions. That a phenomenon or statement may well be *both true and false* — depending on
its context and its place in a process of becoming other than what
it is — is excluded by the logical premise on which these tests are
based. This testing procedure makes for bad mental habits among
young people, who are schooled to take such tests successfully,
and whose careers and future lifeways depend on their scores. But
the thought process demanded by such tests compartmentalizes
and essentially computerizes otherwise rich minds, depriving
young people of their native ability to think organically and to understand the developmental nature of the real world.
Another major presupposition of conventional reason —
one that follows from its concepts of identity and causality — is
that history is a layered series of separate phenomena, a mere
*succession* of strata, each independent of the ones that precede and
follow it These strata may be cemented together by phases, but
these phases are themselves analyzed into components and explored independently of each other. Thus, Mesozoic rock strata
are independent of Cenozoic, and each stratum exists very much
on its own, as do the ones that cement them together. In human
history, the medieval period is independent of the modern, and
the former is connected to the latter by a series of independent
segments, each relatively autonomous in relation to the preceding and subsequent ones. From the standpoint of conventional
reason, it is not always clear how historical change occurs or
what meaning history has. Despite postmodernism and present-day historical relativism, which examine history using conventional reason and thereby ravage it, there was a time in the recent
past when most historians, influenced by theories of evolution
and by Marxism, regarded history as a developmental phenomenon and subsequent periods as at least depending upon prior
ones. It is this tradition that dialectical reason upholds.
The intuitional approach to history is no improvement
over that of conventional reason — indeed, it does the opposite: it
literally dissolves historical development into an undifferentiated
continuum and even into ubiquitous, all-embracing “One.” The
mystical counterpart of mechanico-materialistic stratification is
the reductionism that says that everything is “One” or “interconnected,” that all phenomena originated from a pulse of primal
energy, like the Victorian physicist who believed that when he
pounded his fist on a table, Sirius trembled, however faintly. That
the universe had an origin, whatever it was, does not warrant the
naive belief that the universe still “really” consists of nothing but
i its originating source, any more than an adult human being can
be explained entirely by reference to his or her parents. This way
of thinking is not far removed from the kinetic cause-effect approach of conventional reason. Nor does the “interconnectedness” of all life-forms preclude the sharp distinctions between
prey and predators, or between instinctively guided life-forms
and potentially rational ones. Yet these countless differentiations
reflect innumerable innovations in evolutionary pathways, indeed different kinds of evolution — be they inorganic, organic, or
social. Instead of apprehending things and phenomena as both
differentiated and yet cumulatively related, the mystical alternative to conventional reason tends to see them, to use Hegel’s famous remark, as “a night in which all cows are black.”
Conventional reason, to be sure, has its useful side. Its internal consistency of propositions, irrespective of content, plays
an indispensable role in mathematical thinking and mathematical
sciences, in engineering, and in the nuts-and-bolts activities of
everyday life. It is indispensable when building a bridge or a
house; for such purposes, there is no point in thinking along
evolutionary or developmental lines. If we used a logic based on
anything but the principle of identity to build a bridge or a house,
a catastrophe would no doubt occur. The physiological operations of our bodies, not t 0 speak of the flight of birds and the
pumplike workings of a mammalian heart, depend in great part
upon the principles we associate with conventional reason. To
understand or design a mechanical entity requires a form of
reason that is instrumental and an analysis of reality into its components and their functioning. The truths of conventional reason, based on consistency, are useful in these areas of life. Indeed, conventional reason has contributed immeasurably to our knowledge of the Universe.
For several centuries, in fact, conventional reason held out
a promise to dispel the dogmatic authority of the church the arbitrary behavior of absolute monarchs, and the frightening
ghosts of superstition — and indeed, it did a great deal to fulfill
this promise. But to achieve the consistency that constitutes its
fundamental principle, conventional reason removes ethics from
its discourse and concerns. And as an instrument for achieving
certain ends, the moral character of those ends, the values, ideals,
beliefs, and theories people cherish, are irrelevant to it, arbitrary
matters of personal mood and taste. With its message of identity
and consistency as truth, conventional reason fails us not because
it is false as such but because it has staked out too broad a claim
for its own validity in explaining reality. It even redefines reality
to fit its claim, just as many mathematical physicists redefine
reality as that which can be formulated in mathematical terms. It
should come as no surprise, then, that in our highly rationalized
industrial society, conventional reason has come to seem repellent. Pervasive authority, an impersonal technocracy, an unfeeling science and insensitive, monolithic bureaucracies — the very
existence of all these is imputed to reason as such.
----
Here we find ourselves in something of a quandary. It is obvious
that we cannot do without the much-despised tenets of conventional reason in our everyday life; nor can we do without many
technologies — including sophisticated binoculars to watch birds
and whales, and cameras to photograph them. This being the
case, we conclude, let us turn to an irrational, mystical, or
religious private world to support our moral and spiritual beliefs;
let us seek communion with a mystical “One” even as we work
for corporations to survive. Thus, even as we rail against dualism
and plead for a greater sense of unity, we sharply dualize our
own existence. Even as we may seek an elevated spirituality, communion, and connectedness, we turn to rather mundane gurus,
charismatic personalities, and cultic figures who behave more like
entrepreneurs in the vending of mystical nostrums than financially disinterested guides in attaining moral perfection. Even as
we denounce a materialistic and consumeristic mentality, we ourselves become avid consumers of costly, supposedly spiritual or
ecological products, “green” wares that bear lofty messages. Thus
do the most vulgar attributes of what we regard as the realm of
reason continue to invade our lives in the guise of irrational, mystical, and religious commodities.
Our mailboxes are flooded with catalogues, and our
bookstores are filled with paperbacks that offer us new roads to
mystical communion and a New Age into which we can
withdraw and turn our backs to the harsh realities that constantly
assail us. Often, this mystical withdrawal yields a state of social
quietism that is more dreamlike than real, more passive than active. Preoccupied more with personal change than with social
change, and concerned more with the symptoms of our powerless, alienated lives than with the root causes, we surrender control over the social aspects of our lives, even as they are so
important in shaping our private lives.
But there can be no personal “redemption” without social
“redemption”, and there can be no ethical life without a rational
life. If metaphors with mystical connotations are not to replace
understanding and if obscurantism is not to replace genuine insight — all in reaction to the limitations of conventional reason
and its emphasis on value-free forms of thought — we must examine the alternative form of reason that I have already introduced. This, let me insist, is not a philosophically abstract issue. It
has enormous implications for how we behave as ethical beings
and for our understanding of the nature of nature and our place,
in the natural world. Moreover, it directly affects the kind of
society, sensibility, and lifeways we choose to foster.
Let us grant that the principles of identity, of efficient
causality, and of stratification do apply to a particular commonsensical reality that is rendered intelligible by their use. But when
we go beyond that particular reality, we can no longer reduce the
rich wealth of differentiation, flux, development, organic
causality, and developmental reality to a vague “One” or to an
equally vague notion of “interconnectedness.” A very considerable literature dating back to the ancient Greeks provides the
basis of an *organic* form of reason and a *developmental* interpretation of reality.
With a few notable exceptions, the Platonic dualism of
identity and change reverberated in one way or another
throughout Western philosophy until the nineteenth century,
when Hegel’s logical works largely resolved this paradox by systematically showing that identity, or self-persistence, actually expresses itself *through* change as an ever-variegated unfolding of
“unity in diversity” to use his own words.[3] The grandeur of
Hegel’s effort has no equal in the history of Western philosophy.
Like Aristotle before him, he had an “emergent” interpretation of
causality, of how the implicit becomes explicit through the unfolding of its latent form and possibilities. On a vast scale over the
course of two sizable volumes, he assembled nearly all the
categories by which reason explains reality, and educed one from
the other in an intelligible and meaningful continuum that is
graded into a richly differentiated, increasingly comprehensive,
or “adequate” whole, to use some of his terms.
We may reject what Hegel called his “absolute idealism,”
the transition from his logic to his philosophy of nature, his
teleological culmination of the subjective and objective in a godlike “Absolute,” and his idea of a cosmic Spirit (*Geist*). Hegel
rarefied dialectical reason into a cosmological system that verged
on the theological by trying to reconcile it with idealism, absolute
knowledge, and a mystical unfolding *logos* that he often designated “God.” Unfamiliar with ecology, Hegel rejected natural
evolution as a viable theory in favor of a static hierarchy of Being.
By the same token, Friedrich Engels intermingled dialectical
reason with natural “laws” that more closely resemble the
premises of nineteenth-century physics than a plastic metaphysics
or an organismic outlook, producing a crude dialectical materialism. Indeed, so enamored was Engels of matter and motion as
the irreducible “attributes” of Being that a kineticism based on
mere motion invaded his dialectic of organic development.
To dismiss dialectical reason because of the failings of
Hegel’s idealism and Engels’s materialism, however, would be to
lose sight of the extraordinary coherence that dialectical reason
can furnish and its extraordinary applicability to ecology —
particularly to an ecology rooted in evolutionary development.
Despite Hegel’s own prejudices against organic evolution, what
stands out amid the metaphysical and often theological archaisms in his work is his overall eduction of logical categories
as the subjective anatomy of a developmental reality. What is
needed is to free this form of reason fr om both the quasi-mystical
and the narrowly scientistic worldviews that in the past have
made it remote from the living world; to separate it from Hegel’s
empyrean, basically antinaturalistic dialectical idealism and the
wooden, often scientistic dialectical materialism of orthodox
Marxists. Shorn of both its idealism and its materialism, dialectical reason may be rendered naturalistic and ecological and conceived as a naturalistic form of thinking.
This *dialectical* naturalism offers an alternative to an
ecology movement that rightly distrusts conventional reason.
It can bring coherence to ecological thinking, and it can dispel arbitrary and anti-intellectual tendencies toward the sentimental,
cloudy, and theistic at best and the dangerously antirational, mystical, and potentially reactionary at worst. As a way of reasoning
about reality, dialectical naturalism is organic enough to give a
more liberatory meaning to vague words like *interconnectedness*
and *holism* without sacrificing intellectuality. It can answer the
questions I posed at the beginning of this essay: what nature is,
humamity’s place in nature, the thrust of natural evolution and —
society’s relationship with the natural world. Equally important,
“dialectical naturalism adds an evolutionary perspective to
ecological thinking — despite Hegel’s rejection of natural evolution
and Engels’s recourse to the mechanistic evolutionary
theories of a century ago. Dialectical naturalism discerns
evolutionary phenomena fluidly and plastically, yet it does not divest
evolution of rational interpretation. Finally, a dialectic that has
Been “ecologized,” or given a naturalistic core, and a truly
developmental understanding of reality could provide the basis
for a living ecological ethics.
No general account of dialectical reason can be a substitute for reading Hegel’s works on logic. For all its forced
analyses and doubtful transitions in educing one logical category
from another, Hegel’s *Science of Logic* is dialectical reason in its
most elaborate and dynamic form. This work, in many respects,
absorbed the conventional logic of Aristotle’s *Posterior Analytics*
into the same Greek thinker’s *Metaphysics*, with its bold view of
the nature of reality. I shall therefore not pretend that a broad
description of the dialectic can replace the detailed presentation
Hegel advanced, nor try to force its theoretical unfolding into the
brief “definitions and conclusions” that ordinarily pass for accounts of ideas. As Hegel himself observed in his *Phenomenology of Spirit*: “For the real issue is not exhausted by stating it as an
aim, but by carrying it out; nor is the result the actual whole, but
rather the result together with the process through which it came
about. The aim by itself [“definitions and conclusions”] is a lifeless universal, just as the guiding tendency is a mere drive that as
yet lacks an actual existence; and the bare result is the corpse
which has left the guiding tendency behind it.”[4] Hegel’s dialectic,
in effect, defies the demand for dictionary-style definition. It can
be understood only in terms of the working out of dialectical
reason itself, just as an insightful psychology demands that we
can truly know an individual only when we know his or her entire biography, not merely the numerical results of psychological
tests and physical measurements.
----
Minimally, we must assume that there is order in the world, an
assumption that even ordinary science must make if it is to exist.
Minimally, too, we must assume the existence of growth and
processes that lead to differentiation, not merely the kind of motion that results from push-pull, gravitational, electromagnetic,
and similar forces. Finally, minimally, we must assume that there
is some kind of directionality toward ever-greater differentiation
or wholeness insofar as potentiality is realized in its full
actuality. We need not return to medieval teleological notions of
an unswerving predetermination in a hierarchy of Being to accept this directionality; rather, we need only point to the fact
that there is a generally orderly development in the real world
or, to use philosophical terminology a “logical” development
when a development succeeds in becoming what it is *structured*
to become.
In Hegel’s logical works, as in Aristotle’s *Metaphysics*,
dialectic is more than a remarkable “method” for dealing with
reality. Conceived as the logical expression of a wide-ranging form
of developmental causality, logic, in Hegel’s work, joined hands
with ontology. Dialectic is simultaneously a way of reasoning and
an account of the objective world, with an ontological causality.
As a form of reasoning, the most basic categories in dialectic —
even such vague categories as “Being” and “Nothing” — are differentiated by their own inner logic into fuller, more complex
categories. Each category, in turn, is a potentiality that by means
of eductive flunking, (directed toward an exploration of its latent
and implicit possibilities, yields logical expression in the form of
self-realization, or what Hegel called “actuality” (*Wirklichkeit*).
Precisely because it is also a system of causality, dialectic is
ontological, objective, and therefore naturalstic as-well as a form
of reason. In ontological terms, dialectical causality.is not merely
motion, force, or changes of form but things and phenomena in
development. Indeed, since all Being is Becoming, dialectical
causality is the differentiation of potentiality into actuality, in the
course of which each new actuality becomes the potentiality for
further differentiation and actualization. Dialectic explicates how
processes occur not only in the natural world but in the social.
How the implicit qua a relatively-differentiated form
latent with possibility becomes a more differentiated form that is
true to the way its potential form is-constituted is clarified as
Hegel’s own words. “The plant, for example, does not lose itself
in mere indefinite change,” he writes. It has a distinct directionality — in the case of conscious beings, purpose as will. “From
the germ much is produced when at first nothing was to be seen,
but the whole of what is brought forth, if not developed, is yet
hidden and ideally contained within itself.” It is worth noting, in
this passage, that what may be “brought forth” is not necessarily
developed: an acorn, for example, may become food for a squirrel
or wither On a concrete sidewalk, rather than develop into what it
is potentially constituted to become — notably, an oak tree. ‘The
principle of this projection into existence is that the germ cannot
remain merely implicit’. Hegel goes on to observe, “but is impelled towards development, since it presents the contradiction of being only implicit.”[5]
What we vaguely call the “immanent” factors that produce
a self-unfolding of a development, the Hegelian dialectic regards
as the contradictory nature of a being that is unfulfilled in the
sense that it is only implicit or incomplete. As mere potentiality, it
has not “come to itself,” so to speak. A thing or phenomenon in
dialectical causality remains unsettled, unstable, in tension —
much as a fetus ripening toward birth strains to be born because
of the way it is constituted — until, it develops itself into what it
“should be” in all its wholeness or fullness. It cannot remain in
endless tension or “contradiction” with what it is organize d to
become without warping or undoing itself. It must ripen into the
fullness of its being.
Modern science has tried to describe nearly all phenomena,
in terms of efficient cause or the kinetic impact of forces-on a thing —
or phenomenon, reacting against medieval conceptions of
causality in terms of *final cause* — notably, in terms of the existence
of a deity who impels development, if only by virtue of “His” own
“perfection.” Hegel’s notion of “imperfection” — more appropriately, of “inadequacy” or of contradiction — as an impelling factor
for development partly went beyond both ...efficient and final notions of causality. I say “partly” for a specific reason: the
philosophical archaisms that rim through Hegel’s dialectic weaken
his position from a naturalistic viewpoint. From Plato’s time unify
the beginning of the modern world, theological notions of perfection, infinity, and eternality permeated philosophical thought.
Plato’s “ideal forms” were the “perfect” and the “eternal,” of which
all existential things were copies. Aristotle’s God, particularly as it
was Christianized by the medieval Scholastics, was the “perfect”
One toward which all things strove, given their finite “imperfection” and inherent limitations. In this way, a supranatural ideal
defined the “imperfection” of natural phenomena and thereby
dynamized them in their striving toward “perfection.” There is an
element of this quasitheological thinking in Hegel’s notion of contradiction: the whole course of the dialectic culminates in the “Absolute,” which is “perfect” in its fullness, wholeness, and unity.
Dialectical naturalism, by contrast, conceives finiteness
and contradiction as distinctly *natural* in the sense that things and
phenomena are incomplete and unactualized in their development
— not “imperfect” in any idealistic or supranatural sense.
Until they are what they have been constituted to become, they
exist in a dynamic tension. A dialectical naturalist view has nothing to do with the supposition that things or phenomena fail to
approximate a Platonic ideal or a Scholastic God. Rather;, they are
still in the process of becoming or, more mundanely, *developing*.
Dialectical naturalism thus does not terminate in a Hegelian Absolute at the end of a cosmic developmental path, but rather advances the vision of an ever-increasing wholeness, fullness, and
richness of differentiation and subjectivity.
Dialectical contradiction exists within the structure of a
thing or phenomenon by virtue of a formal arrangement that is
incomplete, inadequate, implicit, and unfulfilled in relation to
what it”should be.” A naturalistic framework does not limit us to
efficient causality with a mechanistic tilt. Nor need we have
recourse to theistic “perfection” to explain the almost magnetic
eliciting of a development. Dialectical causality is uniquely organic because it operates within a development — the degree of
form of a thing or phenomenon, the way in which that form is organized, the tensions or “contradictions” to which its formal ensemble gives rise, and its metabolic self-maintenance and
self-development. Perhaps the most subtle word for this kind of
development is *growth* — growth not by mere accretion but by a
truly immanent process of organic self-formation in a graded and
increasingly differentiated direction.
A distinctive continuum emerges from dialectical causality.
Here, cause and effect are not merely coexisting phenomena or
“correlations,” to use a common positivist term; nor are they
clearly distinct from each other, such that a cause externally impacts upon a thing or phenomenon to produce an effect mechanically. Dialectical causality is cumulative: the implicit or “in itself”
(*an sich*), to use Hegel’s terminology, is not simply replaced or
negated by its more developed explicit or “for itself” (*für sich*);
rather, it is absorbed into and developed beyond the explicit into
a fuller, more differentiated, and more adequate form — the
Hegelian “in and for itself” (*an und für sich*). Insofar as the implicit
is fully actualized by becoming what it is constituted to be, the
process is truly rational, that is to say, it is fulfilled by virtue of its
*internal* logic. The continuum of a development is cumulative,
containing the history of its development.
----
Reality is not simply what we experience: there is a sense in
which the rational has its *own* reality. Thus, there are existing
realities that are irrational and unrealized realities that are rational. A society that fails to actualize its potentialities for human
happiness and progress is “real” enough in the sense that it exists,
but it is less than truly social. It is incomplete and distorted insofar as it merely persists, and hence it is irrational. It is less than
what it should be socially, just as a generally defective animal is
less than what it should be biologically. Although it is “real” in an
*existential sense*, it is unfulfilled and hence “unreal” *in terms of its potentialities*.
Dialectical naturalism asks which is truly real — the
incomplete, aborted, irrational “what-is,” or the most fully
developed, rational “what-should-be.” *Reason,* cast in the form of
dialectical causality as well as dialectical logic, yields an unconventional understanding of reality. A process that follows its immanent self-development to its logical actuality is more properly
‘real” than a given “what-is” that is aborted or distorted and
hence, in Hegelian terms, “untrue” to its possibilities. Reason has
the obligation to explore the potentialities that are latent in any social development and educe its authentic actualization, its fulfillment and “truth” in a new and more rational social dispensation.
It would be philosophically frivolous to embrace the
“what-is” of a thing or phenomenon as constituting its “reality”
without considering it in the light of the “what-should-be” that
would logically emerge from its potentialities. Nor do we ordinarily do so in practice. We rightly evaluate an individual in
terms of his or her known potentialities, and we form understandable judgments about whether the individual has truly “fulfilled” himself or herself. Indeed, in privacy, individuals make
such self-evaluations repeatedly, which may have important effects upon their behavior, creativity, and self-esteem.
The what-is, conceived as the strictly existential, is a slippery “reality” Accepted empirically without qualification, it excludes the past because, strictly speaking, the past no longer “is.”
At the same time, it yields a discontinuity with the future that —
again, strictly speaking — has ye t to “exist.” What is more, the
what-is, conceived in strictly empirical terms, excludes subjectivity — certainly conceptual thought — from any role in the world but a spectatorial one, which may or may not be a “force” in behavior.
In the logic of a strictly empirical philosophy, mind simply
registers or coordinates experience. “Reality” is a given temporal
moment that exists as an experienced segment of an assumed
continuum. The “real” is a frozen “here and now” to which we
merely *add* an adventitious past and *presume* a future in order to
experience reality intelligibly. The kind of radical empiricism advanced by David Hume replaced the notion of Being as Becoming
with the experience of a given moment that renders thinking of
the past as “unreal” in making inferences about the future. This
kind of “reality,” as Hume himself fully sensed, is impossible to
live with in everyday life; hence he was obliged to define continuity, although he did so in terms of custom and habit, not in
terms of causality. Conceiving immediate empirical reality as the
totality of the “real” essentially banishes hindsight and foresight
as little more than mere conveniences. Indeed, a strictly empirical
approach dissolves the logical tissue that integrates the organic,
cumulative continuity of the past with the present and that of
both with the future.
By contrast, in a naturalistic dialectic, both past and future
are part of a cumulative, logical, and objective continuum that includes the present. Reason is not only a means for analyzing and
interpreting reality; it extends the *boundaries* of reality beyond the
immediately experienced present. Past, present, and future are a
cumulatively graded process that thought can truly interpret and
render meaningful. We can legitimately explore such a process in
terms of whether,its potentialities have been realized, aborted, or
warped.
In a naturalistic dialectic, the word *reality* thus acquires two
distinctly different meanings. There is the immediately present
empirical “reality” — or *Realität*, to use Hegel’s language — that
need not be the fulfillment of a potentiality, and there is the dialectical “actuality” — *Wirklichkeit* — that constitutes a complete fulfillment of a rational process. Even though *Wirklichkeit* appears as a
projection of thought into a future that has yet to be existentially
realized, the potentiality from which that *Wirklichkeit* develops is
as existential as the world we sense in direct and immediate ordinary experience. For example, an egg patently and empirically exists, even though the bird whose potential it contains has yet to
develop and reach maturity. Just so, the given potentiality of any
process exists and constitutes the basis for a process that should be
realized. Hence, the potentiality *does* exist objectively, even in empirical terms. *Wirklichkeit* is what dialectical naturalism infer shorn
an objectively given potentiality; it is present, if only implicitly, as
an existential fact, and dialectical reason can analyze and subject it
to processual inferences. Even in the seemingly most subjective
projections of speculative reason, *Wirklichkeit*, the “what-should-be,” is anchored in a continuum that emerges from an objective
potentiality, or “what-is”.
Dialectical naturalism is thus integrally wedded to the objective world — a world in which Being is Becoming. Let me emphasize that dialectical naturalism not only grasps reality as an
existentially unfolding continuum, but it also forms an *objective*
framework for making ethical judgments. The “what-should-be”
becomes an ethical criterion for judging the truth or validity of an
objective “what-is.” Thus ethics is not merely a matter of personal
taste and values; it is factually anchored in the world itself as an objective standard of self-realization. Whether society is “good”
“bad”, moral or immoral, for example, can be *objectively* determined
by whether it has fulfilled its potentialities for rationality and
morality. Potentialities that are themselves actualizations of a dialectical continuum present the challenge of ethical self-fulfillment — not
simply the privacy (of the mind but in the reality of the processual world. Herein lies the only meaningful basis of a truly ethical socialism or anarchism, one that is more than a body of subjective
“preferences” that rest an opinion and taste.
One may well question the validity of dialectical reason by
challenging the concept of *Wirklichkeit*, and its claims to be more
adequate than *Realität*. Indeed, I am often asked: “How do you
know that what you call a distorted ‘untrue’ or ‘inadequate’
reality is not the vaunted ‘actuality’ that constitutes the authentic
realization of a potentiality? Are you not simply making a private
moral judgment about what is ‘untrue’ or ‘inadequate’ and denying the importance of immediate facts that do not support your personal notion of the ‘true’ and the ‘adequate’?”
This question is based on the purely conventional
concepts of validity used by analytical logic. “Immediate facts” —
or more colloquially, “brute facts” — are no less slippery than the
empirical reality to which conventional reason confines itself. In
the first place, it is not relevant to determine the validity of a
process by “testing” it against “brute facts” that are themselves
the epistemological products of a philosophy based on fixities. A
logic premised on the principle of identity, *A equals A*, can hardly
be used to test the validity of a logic premised on the principle
*A equals A and not-A*. The two are simply incommensurable. For
analytical logic, the premises of dialectical logic are nonsense; for
dialectical logic, the premises of analytical logic ossify facticity
into hardened, immutable logical “atoms.” In dialectical reason,
“brute facts” axe distortions of reality since Being is not an agglomeration of fixed entities and phenomena but is always in
flux, in a state of Becoming. One of the principal purposes of
dialectical reason is to explain the nature of Becoming, not simply to explore a fixed Being.
Accordingly, the validity of a concept derived from a
developmental process rather than from “brute facts” must be
“tested “ only by_examining that developmental process, particularly the structure of the potentiality from which the process
emerges and the logic that can be inferred from its potentialities.
The validity of conclusions that are derived from conventional
reason and experience can certainly be tested by fixed “brute
facts”; hence the great success of, say, structural engineering. But
to try to test the validity of actualities that derive from a dialectical exploration of potentialities and their internal logic by using
“brute facts” would be like trying to analyze the emergence of a
fetus in the same way that one analyzes the design and construction of a bridge. Real developmental processes must be tested by a
logic of *processes*, not by a logic of “brute facts” that is analytical,
based on a *datum* or fixed phenomenon.
----
I have emphasized the word *naturalism* in my account of dialectical reason not only to distinguish dialectic from its idealistic and
materialistic interpretations but, more significantly, to show how
it enriches our interpretation of nature and humanity’s place in
the natural world. To attain these ends, I feel obliged to highlight
the overall coherence of dialectical reason as an abiding view of a
developmental reality in its many gradations as a continuum.
If dialectical naturalism is to explain things or phenomena
properly, its ontology and premises must be understood as more
than mere motion and interconnection. A continuum is a more
relevant premise for dialectical reason than either motion or the
interdependence of phenomena. It was one of the failings of
“dialectical materialism” that it premised dialectic on the
nineteenth century’s physics of matter and motion, from which
development somehow managed to emerge. It would be just as
limited to replace the entelechial processes involved in differentiation and the realization of potentiality with “interconnectedness.” A dialectic based merely on a notion of “interconnectedness” would tend to be more descriptive than eductive; it would
not clearly explain how interdependencies lead to a graded entelechial development —that is, to self-formation through the self-realization of potentiality.
To assert that bison and wolves “depend” upon each other
(in a seeming “union of opposites”), or that “thinking like a
rock” a vision borrowed from mystical ecology — will bring us
into greater “connectedness” with the inorganic mineral world,
explains little. But it explains a great deal to study how bison and
wolves were differentiated in the course of evolution from a common mammalian ancestor, or how the organic world emerged
from the inorganic. In the latter cases, we can learn something
about how development occurs, how differentiation emerges
from given potentialities, and what direction these developments
follow. We also learn that a dialectical development is cumulative,
namely that each level of differentiation rests on previous ones.
Some developments enter directly into a given level, others are
proximate to it, and still others are fairly remote. The old never
completely disappears but is reworked into something new. Thus,
as the fossil record tells us, mammalian hair and avian feathers
are later differentiations of reptilian scales, while the jaws of all
animals are a later differentiation of gills.
The nondialectical thinking that is rife in the ecology
movement commonly produces such questions as “What if redwood trees have consciousness that compares with our own?” It is fatuous to challenge dialectical reason with promiscuous
“what-ifs” that have no roots in a dialectical continuum. Every intelligible “if” must itself be a potentiality that can be accounted for as the product of a development. A hypothetical “if” that
floats in isolation, lacking roots in a developmental continuum, is
nonsensical. As Denis Diderot’s delightful character Jacques, in
the picaresque dialogue *Jacques le Fataliste*, exclaimed when his
master peppered him with random if questions: “If, if, if ... if the
sea boiled, there would be a lot of cooked fish!”
The continuum that dialectical reason investigates is a
highly graded, richly entelechial, logically eductive, and self-directive process of unfolding toward ever-greater differentiation, wholeness, and adequacy, insofar as each potentiality is
fully actualized given a specific range of development External
factors, internal rearrangements, accidents, even gross irrationalities may distort or preclude a potential development. But
insofar as order does exist in reality and is not simply imposed
upon it by mind, reality has a rational dimension. More colloquially, there is a “logic” in the development of phenomena, a
*general* directiveness that accounts for the fact that the inorganic
did become organic, as a result of its *implicit capacity* for organicity;
and for the fact that the organic did become more differentiated and
metabolically self-maintaining and self-aware, as a result of potentialities that made for highly developed hormonal and nervous systems.
Stephen Jay Gould may luxuriate in the randomness —
actually, the fecundity — of nature, and poststructuralists may try
to dissolve both natural and social evolution into an aggregation
of unrelated events, but directiveness of organic evolution unremittingly surfaces in even these rather chaotic collections of
“brute facts.” Like it or not, human beings, primates, mammals,
vertebrates, and so forth back to the most elementary protozoans
are a sequential presence in the fossil record itself, each emerging
out of its preceding, if extinct, life-forms. As Gould asserts, the
Burgess Shale of British Columbia attests to a large variety of fossils that cannot be classified into a unilinear “chain of being “ But
far from challenging the existence of directionality in evolution
toward greater subjectivity, the Burgess Shale provides extraordinary evidence of the fecundity of nature. Nature’s fecundity rests
on the existence of chance, indeed variety, as a *precondition* for
complexity in organisms and ecosystems (as my essay “Freedom
and Necessity in Nature” herein argues) and, by virtue of that
fecundity, for the emergence of humanity from potentialities that
involve increasing subjectivity.
Our ontological and eductive premise for dialectical
naturalism, however, remains the graded continuum I have already described — and the Burgess Shale notwithstanding,
human beings are not only *patently* here, but our evolution can be
*explained*. Dialectical reason cuts across the grain of conventional
ways of thinking about the natural world and mystical interpretations of it. Nature is not simply the landscape we see from behind
a picture window, in a moment disconnected from those that
preceded and will follow it; nor is it a vista from a lofty mountain
peak (as I point out in my essay “Thinking Ecologically,” also
herein). Nature is certainly all of these things — but it is significantly more. Biological nature is above all the cumulative
evolution of ever-differentiating and increasingly complex life-forms with a vibrant and interactive inorganic world. Following
in a tradition that goes back at least to Cicero, we can call this
relatively unconscious natural development “first-nature,” It is
first nature in the primal sense of a fossil record that clearly leads
to mammalian, primate, and human life — not to mention its extraordinary fecundity of other life-forms — and it is first nature that exhibits a high degree of orderly continuity in the actualization of potentialities that made for more complex and self-aware
or subjective life-forms. Insofar as this continuity is intelligible, it
has meaning and rationality in terms of its results: the elaboration
of life-forms that can conceptualize, understand, and communicate with each other in increasingly symbolic terms.
In their most differentiated and fully developed forms,
these self-reflexive and communicative capacities are conceptual
thought and language. The human species has these capacities to
an extent that is unprecedented in any other existing life-form.
Humanity’s awareness of itself, its ability to generalize this
awareness to the level of a highly systematic understanding of its
environment in the form of philosophy, science, ethics, and aesthetics, and finally, its capacity to alter itself and its environment
systematically by means of knowledge and technology places it
beyond the realm of the subjectivity that exists in first nature.
By singling out humanity as a unique life-form that can
consciously change the entire realm of first nature, I do not claim
that first nature was “made” to be “exploited” by humanity, as
those ecologists critical of “anthropocentrism” sometimes charge,
the idea of a made world has its origin in theology, notably in the
belief that a supernatural being created the natural world and
that evolution is infused with a theistic principle, both in the service of human needs. By the same token, humans cannot “exploit” nature, owing to a “commanding” place in a supposed “hierarchy” of nature. Words like *commanding*, *exploitation*, and
*hierarchy* are actually social terms that describe how people relate
to each other; applied to the natural world, they are merely
anthropomorphic.
Far more relevant from the standpoint of dialectical
naturalism is the fact that humanity’s vast capacity to alter first
nature is itself a product of natural evolution — not of a deity or
the embodiment of a cosmic Spirit. From an evolutionary view-point, humanity has been *constituted* to intervene actively, consciously, and purposively into first nature with unparalleled
effectiveness and to alter it on a planetary scale. To denigrate this
capacity is to deny the thrust of natural evolution itself toward
organic complexity and subjectivity — the potentiality of first nature to actualize itself in self-conscious intellectuality. One may
choose to argue that this thrust was predetermined with inexorable certainty as a result of a deity, or one may contend that it
was strictly fortuitous, or one may claim — as I would — that there
is a natural *tendency* toward greater complexity and subjectivity in
first nature arising from the very interactivity of matter, indeed a
nisus toward self-consciousness, just what is decisive here is the
compelling fact that humanity’s natural capacity to consciously
intervene into and act upon first nature has given rise to a
“second nature,” a cultural, social, and political “nature”
that today has all but absorbed first nature.
There is no part of the world that has not been profoundly
affected by human activity — neither the remote fastnesses of Antarctica nor the canyons of the ocean’s depths. Even wilderness
areas require protection from human intervention; much that is
designated as wilderness today has already been profoundly affected by human activity. Indeed, wilderness can be said to exist
primarily as a result of a human decision to preserve it. Nearly all
the nonhuman life-forms that exist today are, like it or not, to some
degree in human custody, and whether they are preserved in their
wild lifeways depends largely on human attitudes and behavior.
That second nature is the outcome of evolution in first nature and can thereby be designated as natural does not mean that
second nature is necessarily creative or even fully conscious of itself in any evolutionary sense ; Second nature is synonymous
with society and human internal nature, both of which are undergoing evolution for better or worse. Although social evolution
is grounded in, indeed phases out of, organic evolution, it is also
profoundly different from organic evolution. Consciousness, will,
alterable institutions, and the operation of economic forces and
technics may be deployed to enhance the organic world or carry
it to the point of destruction. Second nature as it exists today is
marked by monstrous attributes, notably hierarchy, class, the
state, private property, and a competitive market economy that
obliges economic rivals to grow at the expense of each other or
perish. This ethical judgment, I may note, has meaning *only* if we
assume that there is potentiality and self-directiveness in organic
evolution toward greater subjectivity, consciousness, self-reflexivity;
by inference, it is the *responsibility* of the most conscious of life-forms —
humanity—to be the “voice” of a mute nature and to act to intelligently foster organic evolution?
If this tendency or *nisus* in organic evolution is denied,
there is no reason why the human species, like any other species,
should not utilize its capacities to serve its own needs or attain its
own “self-realization,” to use the language of mystical ecology, at
the expense of other life-forms that impede its interests and
desires. To denounce humanity for “exploiting” organic nature,
“degrading” it, “abusing” it, and behaving “anthropocentrically”
is simply an oblique way of acknowledging that second nature is
the bearer of moral responsibilities that do not exist in the realm
of first nature. It is to acknowledge that if all life-forms have an
“intrinsic worth” that should be respected, they have it only because human intellectual, moral, and aesthetic abilities have attributed it to them — abilities that no other life-form possesses.
Only human beings can even *formulate* the concept of “intrinsic
worth” and endow it with ethical responsibility. The “intrinsic
worth” of human beings is thus patently exceptional, indeed
extraordinary.
It is essential to emphasize that second nature is, in fact, a
very *unfinished*, indeed inadequate, development of nature as a
whole. Hegel viewed human history as a slaughterbench.
Hierarchy, class, the state, and the like are evidence — and, by no means,
purely accidental evidence — of the unfulfilled potentialities of
nature to actualize itself as a nature that is self-consciously creative.
*Humanity as it now exists is not nature rendered self-conscious.*
The future of the biosphere depends overwhelmingly on whether
second nature can be *transcended* in a new system of social and organic conciliation, one that I would call “free nature” — a nature
that would diminish the pain and suffering that exist in both first
and second nature. Free nature, in effect would be a conscious
and ethical nature, an ecological society that have explored in
detail in my book *Toward an Ecological Society* and in the closing
portions of *The Ecology of Freedom* and *Remaking Society*.
----
The last quarter of the twentieth century has witnessed an appalling regression of rationality into intuitionism, of naturalism into
supernaturalism, of realism into mysticism, of humanism into
parochialism, and of social theory into psychology. Metaphors
replace intelligible concepts and self-interest replaces a humanistic idealism. In increasing numbers people are more concerned
with finding the motives that presumably underlie expressed
views than with the rational content of the views themselves. Argumentation, so necessary for the clarification of ideas, has given
way to “mediation” notably the reduction of authentic intellectual differences and clashing social interests to the minimal, often
trite points that all parties supposedly have in common. Accordingly, real differences are papered over with the lowest level of
dialogue rather than elevated to a creative synthesis or a clear,
open divergence.
To frivolously speak of “biocentrism,” of “intrinsic worth,”
and even metaphorically, of a “biocentric democracy” (to use the
deplorable verbiage of mystical ecology), as though, human
beings were equatable in terms of their “worth” to, say,
mosquitoes — and then ask human beings to bear a moral responsibility to the world of life — is to degrade the entire project of a
meaningful ecological ethics. In this book I contend that nature
can indeed acquire ethical meaning — an *objectively grounded* ethical meaning. Rather than an amorphous body of personalized, often arbitrary values, involves an expanded
view of reality,a dialectical view of natural evolution, and a distinctive — allbeit by no means hierarchical — place for humanity
and society in natural evolution. The social can no longer be
separated from the ecological, any more than humanity can be
separated from nature. Mystical ecologists who dualize the
natural and the social by contrasting “biocentrism” with “anthropocentrism” have increasingly diminished the importance of social theory in shaping ecological thinking. Political action and
education have given way to values of personal redemption,
ritualistic behavior, the denigration of human will, and the virtues of human irrationality. At a time when the human ego, if
not personality itself, is threatened by homogenization and
authoritarian manipulation, mystical ecology has advanced a
message of self-effacement, passivity, and obedience to the “laws
of nature,” which are held to be supreme over the claims of
human activity and praxis. A philosophy must be developed that
breaks with this deadening aversion to reason, action, and social
concern.
I have called this book *The Philosophy of Social Ecology* because I believe that a dialectical naturalism forms the underpinning of social ecology’s most fundamental message: that our
basic ecological problems stem from social problems. It is devoutly to be hoped that the reader will use this book as a means of
entering into my works on social ecology equipped-with an organic way of thinking out the problems they raise and the solutions they offer. In fact, “Thinking Ecologically” forms a direct
transition from the philosophical and ethical to the social and
visionary. Decades of reflection on ecological issues and ideas
have taught me that philosophy, particularly a dialectical
naturalism, does not inhibit our understanding of social theory
and ecological problems. To the contrary, it provides us with the
rational means for integrating them into a coherent whole and establishes a framework for extending this whole in more fecund and innovative directions.
— March 31,1990
[2] The reason for my choice of the name *conventional reason* is that it encompasses two logical traditions that are often referred to interchangeably, as
if they were synonyms. They are in fact distinguishable, *analytical reason*
being the highly formalized and abstract logic that was elaborated out of
Aristotle’s *Posterior Analytics*, and *instrumental reason*, the more concrete
rationality developed by the pragmatic tradition in philosophy. These
two traditions meld, often unconsciously, into the commonsensical
reason that most people use in everyday life; hence the word conventional.
[3] I wish to voice a caveat here. I may be a dialectician, but I am not a
Hegelian, however much I have benefited from Hegel’s work. I do not
believe in the existence of a cosmic Spirit (*Geist*) that finds its embodiment
in the existential world or in humanity. Armed with a cosmic Spirit that
elaborates itself through human history, Hegel tended to blunt the critical thrust of his dialectic and bring the “real” — the given — into conformity with the “actual” — that is, the potential. I follow out the implications
of Hegel’s dialectic along *naturalistic* lines. Hence my view — or my interpretation, if you like — that his project, bereft of a cosmic Spirit, provides
us with a rich view of reality that includes the rational “what-should-be”
as well as the often irrational “what-is.” Dialectical reason is thus ontologically ethical as well as dialectically logical; a guide to rational praxis
as well as a naturalistic explication of Being.
[4] G.W.F. Hegel, *Phenomenology of Spirit*, trans. A. V Miller (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 2–3.
[5] G.W.F. Hegel, *Lectures on the History of Philosophy*, vol. 1, trans. E. S. Haldane and Frances H Simson (New York Humanities Press, 1955), p. 22.
** Toward a Philosophy of Nature:
The Bases for an Ecological Ethics [6]
Few philosophical areas have gained the social relevance in recent
years that nature philosophy, with all its ethical implications, has acquired. A considerable segment of the literate public is now deeply
occupied with seeking a philosophical interpretation of nature as a
grounding for human conduct and social policy. The literature on
the subject has reached truly impressive proportions and has collected a sizable public readership. In fact, it is fair to say that this interest in nature philosophy is comparable to that which Darwinian
evolutionary theory generated a century ago — and it is almost
equally disputatious, with equally important social implications.
But the current interest in society’s relationship to nature
differs basically from the continuing dispute between creationism
and the theory of evolution. It emerges from a deep public concern over the ecological dislocations that uniquely mark our era.
Initially, in the early and mid-seventies, this concern had a largely
technocratic and legalistic focus and centered on problems of pollution, resource depletion, demography, urban sprawl, nuclear
power plants, the increasing incidence of cancer — in short, the
problems of conventional environmentalism.[7] Environmentalists
saw these problems in strictly practical terms and considered
them resolvable by legislative action, public education, and personal example.
The philosophical literature that has emerged in recent
years stems from a significant popular dissatisfaction with strictly
issue-oriented approaches to the current environmental crisis and
reflects the need for a new theoretical turn. It addresses itself to a
basically new concern: to develop an ecologically creative sensibility toward the environment, one that can serve in the highest ethical sense as a guide for human conduct and provide an
awareness of humanity’s “place in nature”[8] These philosophical
works do not deal with nature merely as an environmental
problematic; rather, they advance a vision of the natural world
and raise it to the level of an inspirited metaphysical principle —
without denying the significance of the environmental activism
they seek to transcend. If the often narrow activism of the early
and mid-seventies can be called the politics of environmentalism,
the nature philosophy (which is in no way to be confused with
the philosophy of science) that is surfacing so prominently today
can be called its ethics, and to some degree its social conscience.
Today’s nature philosophies that try to bring humanity and nature into ethical commonality are meant to correct imbalances in a disequilibrated cosmos or in an irrational society.
Characteristically, the academy lags behind in this intellectualization of ecological problems. This problem is serious because the Western philosophical tradition could greatly enrich
the present nature-philosophical turn; yet the academy has
rendered it needlessly technical or worse, reduced it to the
production of mere historical and monographic memorabilia.
Much of what passes for nature philosophy today outside the
campus, therefore, tends to lack roots in the Western philosophical tradition, and such Western traditions as the ecological movement does invoke have a strongly intuitional thrust.
Nor does the academy always add clarity when it does
bring its intellectual equipment to intervene in the discussion.
Today, virtually all nature philosophy is burdened by a massive
number of stultifying prejudices, but the worst of these prejudices
fester precisely in the academy. There, any conjunction of the
words nature and philosophy automatically evokes fears of antiscientific archaisms and premodernist regressions to a static cosmological metaphysics. To speak frankly, the academic mind has
been trained to view nature philosophy as inimical to critical and
analytical thought No less prejudicial in this regard are the
“neo-Marxists,” “post-Marxists,” and empirical anarchists (for whom any
philosophy short of Bertrand Russell’s logical atomism is sheer
theology), who uneasily regard all organicist theories as redolent
of either dialectical materialism or neo-fascist folk philosophies.
Unless such prejudices are dispelled — or at least explored insight”
fully and critically — the terrain of a serious nature philosophy will
be left open to mystical tendencies and intuitions that may well
render any rational discussion of ecological issues impossible.
In any case, the public desire for new nature philosophies
will not disappear, and the works that are appearing to satisfy
this need are no less problematic than the academy’s conventional wisdom on the subject. It will not do for European and
American academics to disparage this trend by speckling it with
learned name-droppings like “neo-Aristotelianism” or by invoking the disparate pedigrees of Schelling, Driesch, Bergson, and Heidegger.
Contemporary excursions into nature philosophy require a
broader philosophical grounding than they normally receive.
Unfortunately, they typically draw their nourishment more from
systems theory than from the Greeks and the Germans, and their
hues are tinted by Asian rather than Western cosmogonies. If
such eclecticism seems discordant to academic philosophical
theorists, I would argue that they must do better, rather than
simply add a new set of prejudices to ones that already exist.
Whether one chooses to regard recent nature-philosophical
works as a loss or benefit to the ecology movement, this much is
clear: if our schooled philosophical theorists turn their backs on
the rising theoretical interest in the meaning of nature and
humanity’s place in it, they will merely cut themselves off further
from some of the most important developments in contemporary
society.
Before we turn to the widely disparate theorists of popular
nature philosophies, we must deal with a problem that unceasingly nags the academic acolytes of modern scientism. Like a troubling and eruptive unconscious, it plagues the philosophical
superego of the academy and some of its self-professed radical
theorists. This philosophical unconscious is “the Tradition,” or
what is more arrogantly called the “archaic” background that
predates Enlightenment — indeed, modern — philosophy. Modern
subjectivistic and scientistic orientations have raised a barrier
against pre-Enlightenment philosophy that permits little of it to
filter through, so that its own origins have become a mystery to
Western philosophy, a frightening specter like the primal
nightmares of childhood that haunt the armored ego of the adult.
True, interest in Aristotle’s *Metaphysics* “remains perennial,” as we
are told, and “does not flag or fail with the passing years, no matter how far the fashion of thought current at the moment may
seem to wander from the confines of Aristotelian tradition.”[9] But
apart from such canonical works, the censor that acts like a screen
on earlier philosophies seems remarkably secure. Heidegger capitalized on this failure (regrettably, in my view) and delved into the
originating thinkers of Western philosophy, arguing that they are
worthy of serious exegesis (although not all of Heidegger’s
“woodpaths” are to be followed).[10] Ontology understandably bears
a fearsome visage when it lacks a social and moral context, and the
concept of Being loses contact with reality when it is subtly assimilated to subjective approaches to reality like Heidegger’s.
Limitations of space make it impossible for me to fully explore the problems that my remarks on these prejudices doubtless
raise. But even some of the best-known theorists of nature
philosophy in the ecology movement today commit an error. Although they may be cognizant of the prejudices and the censoring mechanisms that separate contemporary philosophy from its
own history, they have dug their trenches poorly by defining
themselves against Descartes rather than Kant.
This is by no means an academic issue, nor is it strictly a
philosophical one. The emphasis on Cartesian mechanism as the
original sin that distorted the modern image of nature has been
overstated for reasons that are more programmatic than theoretical.
Villainous as Descartes may seem, it is a certain realpolitik, I
suspect, that demonizes him over Kant For to single out Kant
would necessitate challenging the dubious subjectivism — such as
the subjectivism that Gregory Bateson gives to systems theory —
and quasi-religious transcendentalism now burgeoning in so
much contemporary “antimechanistic” thinking. As a result,
philosophical theories of nature and the objective ecological
ethics derived from them are being created in the false light of the
“epistemological turn” that Kant ultimately gave to Western
philosophy. The ontologically oriented pre-Kantian interpretations of nature remain as ambiguous in the ecology movement as in the academy.
But premodern and particularly Presocratic philosophy is
not the dead dog that conventional philosophy depicts it as being.
I am not concerned, for the present, with the *specific* speculations
that pre-Kantian philosophies advanced — particularly those of the
Presocratics. Rather, I am concerned with their *intentions* and with
the *kind* of unities they tried to foster. What is important, as
Gregory Vlastos has so admirably emphasized, is that they
authentically voiced an objectivity permeated by ethics. Indeed, in
contrast to the naturalism that became so fashionable in American
academies during the 1930s and 1940s, the unifying feature of the
Ionian, Eleatic, Heraclitean and Pythagorean trends is precisely
their conviction that the universe had in some sense a moral character irrespective of human purposes. So alien is this proposition
to the post-Kantian era that it is dismissed as “archaic” and
“teleological” almost as a knee-jerk reaction.[11] Yet one cannot simply dismiss the fact that such great themes as Being, Form, Motion and Causality were once infused with moral meaning. In fact
they permeate speculative philosophy to this day. The *various*
ways in which the Presocratics explained the *arche* of the world
followed out the logic of this moral meaning.
The very ability to know implies that the world is orderly
and intelligible and that it lends itself to rational interpretation
because it is rational. From Thales to Hegel, philosophy consistently retained this essential orientation. As Lawrence J. Henderson wrote in his immensely influential 1912 work
*The Fitness of the Environment*, the “idea of purpose and order are among the
first concepts regarding their environment which appear, a
vague anticipation of philosophy and science, in the minds of
men.” For Henderson, to be sure, it was the “advent of modern
science” that validated universal order — in the form of natural
law; Darwin’s hypothesis of natural selection, in turn, validated
natural law “as the basis of purpose,” specifically the “new
scientific concept of fitness,” and thereby rescued speculative
thought from the “dogma of final causes.”[12] But what is important in Henderson’s remarks is that he regards the world as intelligible, not the specific content of that intelligibility.
Hellenic thought, by the same token, was pointedly moral
*insofar as it saw the world as rational* — that is, its rationality and intelligibility were equivalent to its morality. However intuitively or
consciously, the Hellenic notion of *nous* — mind — constituted the
world or inhered in it. Precisely because one could explain the
world, the world was meaningful. Nor did Presocratic thought
stop at partial explanations of order; it tried to explain it to the
fullest. Accounts of the *arche* of the world — its active substance —
are redolent with meaning, such as water (which perhaps alludes
kinship) and the “unbounded” or “*aer*” (which historians of
Greek philosophy now regard as “soul,” the “breath of life”).
This sense of reality as pregnant, fecund, and immanently
self-elaborating still provides direction for an ecological
philosophy, however arguable the nature philosophies of the pre-Kantian
past may be. Of particular interest here are the Presocratics. Emphasis on the Presocratics’ “naivete,” their “ontological need” (to use one of Theodor Adorno’s many unfortunate phrases), and
their “monism” has all too cheaply obscured this possibility.
That Presocratic thought was riddled by demonstrably false archaisms is beside the point. It is its orientation that concerns us,
not its ontological merits, and its animistic aspects are such as
might be expected in a transition from the mythopoeic world to
the world of Plato and Aristotle. And in contrast to Heidegger,
we should not view the Presocratics as having an “authentic,”
prelapsarian relationship with Being but as points of departure
for the richer philosophical insights of Plato, Aristotle, and the
other philosophers who constitute the Western philosophical
tradition. *My high valuation of the Presocratics here is purely heuristic*: I do not intend to argue for their notion of “cosmic justice” —
which was patently an extrapolation of the democratic *polis* into
the natural world — or for adherence to their view that nature is
“just” in any other sense. Rather, I wish to emphasize the importance of searching for values that can be grounded in nature — more basically, in natural evolution.
Despite their “naivete,” the Pythagorean *arche* — form — and
ideals of limit, *kosmos* (order combined with beauty), and *krasis*
(equilibrium) have a remarkable, indeed alluring richness. The
Pythagorean notion of form, for example, is essential for understanding holism, for it adds the formal concept of *arrangement* to
the numerical notion of *sum*. The notion of form as the expression
of the good and the beautiful renders virtue cosmically immanent.
More radically, the Presocratics anchored their
interpretation of nature in the notion of *isonomia* (equality), which includes
the equality of the very elements that make up the world.
Philosophers from Anaximander to Empedocles had a thoroughgoing respect for a ubiquitous principle of equality. So consciously did they hold the principle, that Alcmaeon used the term
*monarchy* with opprobrium to characterize the “mastery” or
“supremacy” of one cosmic power over another. *Krasis* is not the
mechanical equipoise of contrasting powers but, more organically, their blending and, in the sequence of phenomena (initially, in.
Greek medical theory), their rotation. “As in the democratic *polis*
The demos rules by turn, so the hot could prevail in summer
without injustice to the cold, if the latter had its turn in the
winter,” Vlastos observes, highlighting the parallels between the
Athenian political system and this notion. “And if a similar and
concurrent cycle of successive supremacy could be assumed to
hold among the powers in the human body, then the *krasis* of
man and nature would be perfect.”[13]
Empedocles thoroughly naturalized this “elegant tissue of
assumptions,” as Vlastos calls these parallels between society and
nature. His concept of “roots” as distinguished from “elements,”
undifferentiated “Being,” and “atoms” vastly enlarged the implicit Hellenic notion of an immanently generative nature to a
point unsurpassed even by Aristotle. The “roots,” as Francis
Cornford observes, are “equal in status or lot”; they rotate their
“rule” with their own unique “honor,” for in no case is the
universe a “monarchy” and none of its powers can claim even the
primacy that Thales gave to fluidity and Anaximenes to soul.[14]
Presocratic thought was consciously infused by a far-reaching
notion of cosmic justice, or *dikaisyne*. This concept of justice extends beyond social and personal issues to nature itself. For
the Presocratics, “justice is no longer inscrutable moira, imposed
by arbitrary forces with incalculable effect. Nor is she the goddess
Dike, moral and rational enough, but frail and unreliable.” Unlike
Hesiod’s Dike, this justice is one with nature itself and “could no
more leave the earth than the earth could leave its place in the firmament.”[15]
Its opposite, *adikaisyne*, marks every transgression of
cosmic justice — of the law of the measure and the *peras* or limit of
things and relationships. It demands reparation and the restoration of harmony.
Nature, in effect, appeared as a commonwealth, a *polis*,
whose *isonomia* effaced the “distinctions between two grades of
being — divine and mortal, lordly and subservient, noble and
mean, of higher and lower honor. It was the ending of these distinctions that made nature autonomous and therefore completely
and unexceptionally ‘just’ Given a society of equals, it was assumed, justice was sure to follow, for none would have the power
to dominate the rest. This assumption ... had a strictly physical
sense. It was accepted not as a political dogma but as a theorem in
physical inquiry. It is, none the less, remarkable evidence of the
confidence which the great age of Greek democracy possessed in
the validity of the democratic idea — a confidence so robust that it
survived translation into the first principles of cosmology and
medical theory.[16]
----
Naive as the Presocratic view may be with all its archaisms, a nature philosophy that is more than the simple contest between mechanism and organicism encountered today would serve to
clarify the wayward fortunes of Western philosophy and challenge the limits it has imposed on ecological ethics. Ironically, the
founders of modern science — Copernicus, Kepler, and Tycho
Brahe — were raging Pythagoreans. What early Renaissance
thought and science rescued from the ancients was not *isonomia*
but form, as well as the shared premise of all speculative reason
that nature is an intelligible *kosmos*. Descartes never challenged
this conceptual framework — he merely gave it a mechanical
form, alluring and subversive for its time.
It was Kant — a near Jacobin — who made the most significant turn in Western philosophy with his “Copernican revolution,” the “epistemological turn.” Kant finally denatured nature
of its Presocratic remnant by removing the material “grade of
being” altogether. Things-in-themselves ceased to be things at all
for cognitive purposes, and one grade of Being effectively ceased
to exist. Kant left us alone with our own subjectivity. “Kant does
not, like all earlier philosophers, investigate objects,” as Karl
Jaspers incisively summarized the issue; “what he inquires into is
our knowledge of objects. He provides no doctrine of the
metaphysical world, but a critique of the reason that aspires to
know it. He gives no doctrine of Being as something objectively
known, but an elucidation of existence as the situation of our consciousness. Or, in his own words, he provides no ‘doctrine’ but a ‘propaedeutics.’” Accordingly, Kantian categories have objective
validity only insofar as they remain within the limits of possible
experience. After Kant, “metaphysics in the sense of objective
knowledge of the supersensible or as ontology, which teaches
being as whole, is impossible.”[17]
As liberating as this innovation was from absolute empiricism, which renders its own experience in a world of pure Being, it was not liberating from absolutes generally. Kant himself made a sweeping intellectualization of objectivity. Although
he acknowledged a noumenal world that is “supersensible” or
“unknowable” and that constitutes the originating source of the
perceptions that his categories synthesize into authentic
knowledge, he opened the way to an epistemological focus on
*systems of knowledge* rather than a naturalistic focus on
*systems of facts*. Facticity itself was absorbed within systems of knowledge,
and the Greek *onta*, the “really existing things,” were displaced by
*episteme*, our “knowledge” of the now “unknowable” *onta*. Hegel
ridiculed the patent contradiction of knowing that an “unknowable” was unknowable — but Kant had dug a veritable trench
around philosophy that excluded nature as ontology and that
rendered thought into Being. With Kant’s agnostic and essentially skeptical outlook, his epistemological turn became absolutized in philosophy.
Lost in this development were the *onta* that alone constitute the underpinnings of nature philosophy, which now had
to be distinguished from Kantian philosophies of the nature of
knowing.[18] Hegel heaped scorn on the notion of the thing-in-itself,
whose very thinghood by definition requires determinations and in fact bears the imprint of the Kantian categories. But
even Hegel ended in the subjectivity of the Absolute. For Hegel,
after all the toil of Spirit, object and subject finally come to rest
in Mind — in knowledge as self-knowing in all its totality — and it
was not for sentimental reasons that Hegel’s *Encyclopedia* ended, with a quotation from Aristotle that exults “thought [that]
thinks on itself because it shares the notion of the object of
thought.”[19] A century later, Husserl’s process of *epoche* bracketed
out the natural world in order to establish the logical necessity
on which it ultimately hangs; Heidegger regarded *Dasein* as the
human existent and royal road to Being. Both distilled reality
into intellection, and the formalizations of the human mind became the exclusive point of entry into Being. Only insofar as
these formalizations become Being itself can one call Heidegger’s or Husserl’s philosophical strategy ontological.
Nor has ecological philosophy breached the Kantian
trench. Rather, it is a captive within it without even knowing it.
Gregory Bateson, the most widely read of its gurus, makes an almost wholly subjective interpretation of the notorious Mind-Nature relationship. In trying to “build the bridge” between
“form and substance,” Bateson emphasizes only too correctly that
Western science began with the “wrong half” of the chasm —
atomistic materialism. Today many ecologically oriented readers
are attracted to his supplantation of matter with mind and to his
conjoining of fact (whatever that means for him) with value. But
quite systematically, Bateson turns any interrelational system at
all into “Mind” and hence makes it subjective. (This notion also
feeds into quasi-super naturalistic visions of reality — generally
Eastern in origin — which curiously tend to transcend the natural
world rather than explain it.) That “Mind is empty; it is no-thing,”
for Bateson, means literally that it is no *thing* at all. Hence, only
“ideas are immanent, embodied in their examples. And the examples [the material embodiments of ideas] are, again, no-things.
The claw, as an example, is not the *Ding an sich*; it is precisely not
the ‘*thing in itself*’ Rather, it is what mind makes of it, namely, an
example of something or other.”[20]
This is not merely a subjectivist variant of Kantianism; it is
a denial of thinghood as such. A true son of the epistemological
turn, Bateson claims that “all experience is subjective ... our
brains make the images that we think we ‘perceive.’” Indeed, “occidental culture” lives under the “illusion” that its own “visual
image of the external world” has ontological reality. Even as
Bateson dismisses ontological properties as such, he smuggles
them back into his own work as systems. Although his argument
against “atomies” takes on the appearance of an argument
against presuppositions, Bateson’s own view is actually overloaded with presuppositions — his whole thesis, he says elsewhere, is “based on the premise that mental function is immanent
in the interaction of differentiated ‘parts’.” [21]
Batesonian mentalism is nourished by the cybernetic idea
that perceptions are parts of a system, not isolates, or as Bateson
calls them, “atomies.” He intends this to mean that the differentiae that form an aggregate of interacting parts are not spatial,
temporal, or substantial; they are relational. The interaction between a subject and object forms a kind of unit system that exists
within ever-larger systems, be they communities, societies, the
planet, the solar system, or ultimately the universe. Bateson
designates these systems as “Minds” — or more precisely, as a
hierarchy of Minds,” much like Arthur Koestler’s holarchy,
with its sublevels of “holons” that extend from subatomic particles, through atoms, molecules, organelles, cells, tissues, and organs, up to living organisms, which have their own scala
naturae.[22]
Bateson’s view that context fixes meaning is not very new
if one knows anything about Whitehead. But cybernetics, too, is
uncritically presupposed. That cybernetics could simply be
another form of mechanism — electronic rather than mechanical — eludes him, as it seems to elude most of its acolytes. Feedback loops are as mechanistic as flywheels, however different the
physics involved may be. Cyberneticians engage in a reductionism similar to that which guided mechanical thinking in
Newton’s day, except that Newton’s was based on matter rather
than energy. The ecological cybernetics of Howard Odum, whose
tunnel vision perceives only the flow of calories through an
ecosystem, is as shallow philosophically as it is useful practically
within its own narrow limits. For its more mystical acolytes,
cybernetics combines with Eastern and Native American
spirituality to become a “spiritual mechanism” that eerily parallels the failings of materialist mechanism, without the latter’s
contact with reality. A deadening vocabulary of information, inputs, outputs, feedback, and *energy* — terminology largely born from
wartime research on radar and servo-mechanisms for military
guidance systems[23] — replaces such once-vibrant words as
knowledge, dialogue, explanation, wisdom, and *vitality*.
As critics of Bateson’s view and of cybernetics generally
have been quick to point out, hierarchies of “Mind” have
authoritarian implications.[24] Koestler was acutely conscious of
this problem in his notion of “holarchy,” with its hierarchies of
“holons”;[25] but Bateson, if anything, is given to using examples
that accentuate the authoritarian features of his outlook. As
Bateson describes “an alternating ladder of calibration and feedback up to larger and larger spheres of relevance and more and more abstract information and wider decision,” he warns that
within the system of police and law enforcement,
and indeed in all hierarchies, it is most undesirable
to have direct contact between levels that are non-consecutive. It is not good for the total organization
to have a pipeline of communication between the
driver of the automobile [who is ticketed for violating a speed limit] and the state police chief. Such
communication is bad for the morale of the police
force. Nor is it desirable for the policeman to have
direct access to the legislature, which would undermine the authority of the police chief.... In legal
and administrative systems, such jumping of logical
levels is called *ex post facto* legislation. In families,
the analogous errors are called *double binds*. In
genetics, the Weissmannian barrier which prevents
the inheritance of acquired characteristics seems to
prevent disasters of this nature. To permit direct influence from somatic state to genetic structure
might destroy the hierarchy of organization within
the creature.[26]
This is sociobiology with a vengeance. Nor was one of the
outstanding founders of systems theory, Ludwig von Bertalanffy,
immune to this tendency when he observed that “the behavior of
animals such as rats, cats, and monkeys provides the necessary
bases for interpretation and control of human behavior; what appears to be special in man is secondary and ultimately to be reduced to biological drives and primary needs.”[27]
Bertalanffy’s “general system theory” — with which he
seeks to replace Cartesian mechanism, “one-way causality, and
“unorganized complexity” — hardly solves the problems that
cybernetic mechanism raises. Ultimately, the thinking in both
cases is similar: a general system theory based on a worldview
of “organized complexity” is essentially a cybernetic system that
is “open” rather than “closed.” Bertalanffy admits that general
system theory is still mechanistic in the sense that it presupposes a “mechanism” that is, structural arrangements. Although it is quite true that “in behavioral parlance, the
cybernetic model is the familiar S-R [stimulus-response] ...
scheme” and simply replaces “*linear causality*” with
“*circular causality* by way of the feedback loop,” the claims advanced by a
general system theory to encompass “multivariable interaction
maintenance of wholes in the counteraction of component parts,
multilevel organization into systems of ever higher order, differentiation centralization, progressive mechanization steering
and trigger causality, regulation evolution toward higher organization teleology and goal-directedness in various forms
and ways, etc.,” are generally more programmatic than real and
incorporate some of the most authoritarian and mechanistic attributes of cybernetics. That the “elaboration of this program has only just begun... and is beset with difficulties” is an understatement.[28]
The issue of development — specifically evolution — is crucial to nature philosophy, but a solution to the problem of why
development occurs, why order and complexity emerge from
lesser degrees of order and simplicity, remains markedly absent
from systems theory. None of the systems theories come close to
an explanation of development and it is not at all clear that the
explanatory powers of cybernetics and systems theory can encompass it. To my knowledge, the only “breakthrough” in this
regard that lends credibility to Bertalanffy’s sweeping claims for
the explanatory potential of general system theory has been Ilya
Prigogine’s mathematical elaboration of the organizing role of
positive feedback.[29] Prigogines work essentially utilizes the
symmetry-breaking effects of positive feedback (or more bluntly,
disorder) as a means for creating “order” at various levels of
organization.
As valuable as this approach may be within the realm of
systems theory itself, particularly in its applications to chemistry,
the spontaneous structuration that it describes does so as the
result of causes no less mechanistic than Bateson s ladder of
“Minds” and Koestler’s hierarchy of “holons.” Certainly, no systems theory I have cited explains *why* one “level of organization”
supersedes or incorporates another; at best, they describe only
*how*, and even these descriptions are woefully incomplete.
Bateson’s stochastic strategy for “explaining” sequence, for example, merely correlates random genetic mutations (or worse,
point mutations, which are piecemeal as well as random) with a
“selective process” that is remarkably passive. Natural selection
merely tells us that the “fittest” survive environmental changes. If
all we know about evolutionary development is that amidst a
flurry of utterly random mutations, the organisms that are
capable of surviving are those that are the “fittest” to survive — a
circular thesis — then we know very little about evolution indeed.
It is not clear whether cybernetics and systems theory can
extend beyond mere *interaction*, as distinguished from authentic
*development*. We certainly have no “system” or “Mind” other than
mere interaction that explains it in these theories. An “interaction” cannot be construed as a relationship unless it is meaningful. To call the mere physical fact that one human being stumbles
over another “intersubjectivity,” for example, degrades the very
meaning of the word *subjective*. The encounter of one body with
another merely produces a form of physical contact. The “interaction” becomes “intersubjective” only when the two persons address each other —
possibly with friendly recognition, possibly
with expletives, possibly even with blows. Moreover, in view of
recent “formalizations” of even radical social theories, I cannot
emphasize too strongly that attempting to understand this “interaction” in all its possible forms and meanings requires knowing
the social and psychological context in which it occurred — that is
to say, the history or dialectic, however trivial, that lies buried
within the “intersubjectivity” that results from the “interaction.”
----
We can certainly criticize cybernetics’ misuse of the concept of
*hierarchy* — a strictly social term — to refer to degrees of complexity
and organization. But ultimately, cybernetics and systems approaches to ecological issues are not subject to immanent critique.
Like Kantian and neo-Kantian philosophies, they are basically
self-sufficient and self-enclosed. Although Kant’s conclusions do
not follow completely from his premises, his very errors have
served as correctives for his successors. Translated into the language of systems theory, Kantianism and its subjective sequelae
are sufficiently closed that their errors become the self-corrective
source of perpetuating Kant’s “Copernican revolution?”
That Kant’s epistemological turn greatly broadened
philosophical thought is hardly arguable. Kant’s elaboration of
an epistemology and the introduction of the subject as both observer and participant in cohering knowledge and reality filled a
major lacuna in Western philosophy. Definitely arguable, however, are the imperial claims that this subjectivism advanced, the
totalization of reality and the arrogant exclusivity it staked out for
itself. Hegel’s brilliant criticism of Kant, while indubitably
shrewd, did not damage these imperial claims; indeed, to some
degree it performed a corrective function for neo-Kantians of
later generations.
If subjectivistic approaches to nature and those based on
systems theory must be challenged, we are obliged to formulate
new premises that provide coherence and meaning to natural
evolution. The truth or falsity of a nature philosophy will lie in
the truth or falsity of its description of an unfolding reality — in
*evolution*, as we are beginning to know it in nature today, and as
this natural evolution grades into social evolution and ethics.
We must not, however, once again rear the hoary myth of a
“presuppositionless philosophy” but choose our presuppositions
carefully and adequately so that they impart coherence and
meaning.
Our first presupposition is that we have the right to
*attribute* properties to nature based on the best of our knowledge,
the right to assume that certain attributes as well as contexts are
*self-evident* in nature. This assumption is immediately problematic
for a vast number of academic philosophers — although, ironically,
it is no problem for most scientists. The great Renaissance
notion that “matter” and “motion” are basic attributes of nature, its
most underlying properties (just as metabolism is a basic property
of life), remains a prevalent *scientific* assumption well into our
own time, however much the meanings of the terms *matter* and
*motion* have changed.
It remained for Diderot in his extraordinary *D’Alembert’s Dream*
to propose the crucial trait of nature that transforms mere
motion into development and directiveness: the notion of
*sensibilite*, an internal *nisus*, that is commonly translated as “sensitivity.” [30] This immanent fecundity of “matter” — as distinguished
from motion as mere change of place — scored a marked advance
over the prevalent mechanism of La Mettrie and, by common acknowledgement, anticipated nineteenth-century theories of
evolution and, in my view, recent developments in biology. Yet
*D’Alembert’s Dream*’s very title forewarns readers of Diderot’s candid sense of doubt of his own “likely story,” given the limited
scientific knowledge of the time.
*Sensibilite* implies an active concept of matter that yields
increasing complexity, from the atomic level to the brain. Continuity is preserved through this development without any
reductionism; indeed, in the scala naturae dynamized by
Diderot’s avowed Heraclitean bias for flux, there is a *nisus* for
complexity, an *entelechia* that emerges from the very nature,
structure, and form of potentiality *itself*, given varying degrees
of the organization of “matter.” From this potentiality and the
actualization of the potentialities of various organisms, *sensibilite*
initiates its journey of self-actualization and emergent form.
Diderot’s holism, in turn, is one of the most conspicuous features of
*D’Alembert’s Dream*. An organism achieves its unity and
sense of direction from the contextual wholeness of which it is
part, a wholeness that imparts directiveness to the organism and
reciprocally receives directiveness from it.
Apart from their systematic and mathematical treatment of
feedback, cybernetics and systems theory can add little to this
idea, advanced by an authentic and largely unacknowledged
genius who died almost two centuries ago. Not only did the active and directive “matter” that Diderot advanced with his notion
of *sensibilite* mark a radical breach with Renaissance and Enlightenment mechanism, but its relevance as “sensitivity,” however metaphoric the terminology, is radically important for
understanding current developments in natural science.
A second presupposition is the *alternative* pathway to Kantianism that Hegel opened up with his own phenomenological
strategy in the richly dialectical approach of the
*Phenomenology of Spirit*
In Hegel’s own description of this strategy: insofar as the
*Phenomenology* “has only phenomenal knowledge for its object,
this exposition seems not to be Science, free and self-moving in its
own peculiar shape; yet from this standpoint it can be regarded
as the path of the natural consciousness which presses forward to
true knowledge; or as the way of the Soul which journeys
through the series of its own configurations as though they were
the stations appointed for it by its own nature, so that it may
purify itself for the life of the Spirit, and achieve finally, through a
completed experience of itself, the awareness of what it really is
in itself.” This “pressing forward” is immanent to true knowledge, for short of finding its goal, “no satisfaction is to be found at
any of the stations along the way.”[31]
Like Lukács, and unlike the academic fluff who have
vitiated Hegel’s strong reality principle, I share Engels’s view that
the *Phenomenology* may be regarded as “a parallel of the embryology and the paleontology of the mind, a development of individual consciousness through its different stages, set in the
form of an abbreviated reproduction of the stages through which
the consciousness of man has passed in the course of history.”[32]
To a remarkable extent, although by no means consistently, the
self-movement of consciousness in the *Phenomenology* parallels
the self-movement of consciousness in historical reality, although
the strategy is captive to rational reality and the ethical universe
it opens for ecology.
Taking as our presuppositions Diderot’s concept of
*sensibilite* in “matter” and Hegel’s phenomenological strategy, we
emerge with a fascinating possibility. Speaking metaphorically, it
is nature itself that seems to “write” natural philosophy and ethics,
not logicians, positivists, neo-Kantians, and heirs of Galilean
scientism. According to a fairly recent revolution in astrophysics
(possibly comparable to the achievements of Copernicus and
Kepler), the cosmos is opening itself up to us in new ways that
demand an exhilaratingly speculative turn of mind and a more
qualitative approach to natural phenomena than in the past. It is
becoming increasingly tenable to hold that the entire universe is
the cradle of life — not merely our own planet or possibly planets
like it. The formation of all the elements from hydrogen and
helium, their combination into small molecules and later into self-forming macromolecules, and finally the organization of these
macromolecules into the constituents of life and possibly mind follow a sequence that challenges Bertrand Russell’s image of
humanity as an accidental spark in a meaningless void. The
presence of complex organic molecules in the vast reaches of the
universe is replacing the classical image of space as a void with an
understanding of space as a restlessly active chemogenic ground
for an astonishing sequence of increasingly complex chemical
compounds. Recent theories about the formation of DNA that are
modeled on the activity of crystalline replication (a notion advanced as early as 1944 by Erwin Schrodinger) suggest how
genetic guidance and evolution itself might have emerged to form
an Interface between the inorganic and organic.[33]
The point is that we can no longer be satisfied with the
theory of an inert “matter” that fortuitously aggregates into life.
The universe bears witness to a *developing* — not merely moving —
substance, whose most dynamic and creative attribute is its unceasing capacity for self-organization into increasingly complex
forms. Form plays a central role in this developmental and
growth process, while function is an indispensable correlate. The
orderly universe that makes science possible and its highly concise logic — mathematics — meaningful presupposes the correlation of form with function.
In life — a *graded* development beyond the chemogenic
crucible that we call the universe — metabolism and development
establish another elaboration of *sensibilite*: symbiosis. Recent data
support the applicability of Peter Kropotkin’s mutualistic
naturalism not only to relationships between species but among
complex cellular forms. As biologist William Trager ironically
remarked a decade ago about the “struggle for existence” and the
“survival of the fittest”: “few people realize that mutual cooperation between different kinds of organisms — symbiosis — is just as
important, and that the ‘fittest may be the one that most helps
another to survive.”[34]
Indeed, the cellular structure of all multicellular organisms
is itself testimony to a symbiotic arrangement that renders complex life-forms possible. The eukaryotic cell — a cell that makes up
an organism — is a highly functional symbiotic arrangement of
the less complex and more primal prokaryotes, or single-celled organisms, and evolved in an anaerobic world long before our
highly oxygenated atmosphere was formed. The work of Lynn
Margulis gives us reason to believe that eukaryotic flagella
derived from anaerobic spirochetes; that mitochondria derived
from prokaryotic bacteria that were capable of respiration as well
as fermentation; and that plant chloroplasts derived from blue-green algae (cyanobacteria).[35]
If Manfred Eigen is correct that evolution “appears to be
an inevitable event, given the presence of certain matter with
specified autocatalytic properties and under the maintenance of
the finite (free) energy flow [solar energy] necessary to compensate for the steady production of energy,” then our very concept
of matter has to be radically revised.[36] The prospect that life and
all its attributes are latent in matter as such, that biological evolution is deeply rooted in symbiosis or mutualism, suggests that
what we call matter is actually active substance.
The traditional dualism between the living and nonliving
worlds, between organisms and their abiotic ecosystems, is being
replaced with the more challenging notion that life “makes much
of its own environment,” to use Margulis’s words. From an
ecological viewpoint, in which life is in its environment and not
isolated from, it, the Weissmannian barrier that conveniently
separates genetic from somatic changes ceases to be meaningful.
“Certain properties of the atmosphere, sediments, and hydrosphere are controlled by and for the biosphere”; by comparing
lifeless planets such as Mars and Venus with the Earth, Margulis
notes that the high concentration of oxygen in our atmosphere is
anomalous in contrast with the carbon dioxide atmospheres of
other planets. Moreover, “the concentration of oxygen in the
Earth’s atmosphere remains constant in the presence of nitrogen,
methane, hydrogen, and other potential reactants.” Life-forms, in
effect, play an active role in maintaining a relatively constant
supply of free oxygen molecules in the Earth’s atmosphere. If the
anomalies of the Earth’s atmosphere “are far from random,” much
the same can be said for the temperature of the Earth’s surface and
the salinity of its oceans, whose stability seems to be a function of
life on the planet. The “natural selection” of Darwinian evolution
may itself be the product of life-forms, which presumably filter out
some genetic changes.[37]
Even the Modern Synthesis, the neo-Darwinian model of
organic evolution that has been in force since the early 1940s, has
been challenged as too narrow and perhaps too mechanistic in its
outlook. Its thesis of slow-paced evolutionary change emerging
from the interplay of small variations, which are “selected” for
their adaptability to the environment, is no longer as tenable as it
once seemed based on the fossil record. Evolution seems instead to
have been rather more sporadic, marked by occasional changes of
considerable rapidity, then long periods of stasis. The “Effect
Hypothesis,” advanced by Elizabeth Vrba, suggests that evolution
includes an immanent striving, not merely random mutational
changes filtered by external selective factors. As one observer
notes, “Whereas species selection puts the forces of change on environmental conditions, the Effect Hypothesis looks to internal
parameters that affect the rates of speciation and extinction.”[38]
Indeed, the theory of small, gradual point mutations (a
theory that accords with the Victorian notion of strictly fortuitous
evolutionary change, much like the Victorian image of the
economic marketplace) can be challenged on genetic grounds
alone. Not only genes but chromosomes, too, may be altered
chemically and mechanically.. Genetic changes may range from
“simple” point mutations, through jumping genes and transposable elements, to major chromosomal rearrangements. Major
morphological changes may thus result from mosaics of genetic
change. This dynamic raises the intriguing possibility of a directiveness to genetic change itself, not simply a promiscuous and
purely fortuitous randomness, and an environment largely
created by life itself, not by forces exclusively external to it.
Neither mysticism nor anthropocentrism is involved in an
ecological view that ontologically graides natural history into social history without sacrificing the unity of either. Nor is it a supernatural fallacy to ultimately derive the human brain from an
actively chemogenic universe that is self-forming and immanently entelechial. Although Hans Driesch gave entelechy a bad
name, the concept derives from Aristotle, not from Driesch’s confused neo vitalism.
The fallacies of classical Greek cosmology generally lie
less in its ethical orientation than in its dualistic view of nature.
For all its emphasis on speculation at the expense of experimentation, ancient cosmology erred most when it tried to join the
self-organizing, fecund nature it had inherited from the Ionians
with a vitalizing force alien to the natural world itself. The self-organizing properties of nature were replaced with Parmenides’
Dike — like Bergson’s *elan vital*, a latently dualistic cosmology that
could not trust nature to develop on its own spontaneous
grounds, any more than ruling social and political strata trust the
body politic to manage its own affairs.
These archaisms, with their theological nuances and their
tightly formulated teleologies, have been justly viewed as socially
reactionary traps. They tainted the works of Aristotle and Hegel
as surely as they mesmerized the medieval Schoolmen. Classical
nature philosophy erred not in its project of trying to elicit an
ethics from nature, but in the spirit of domination that poisoned it
from the start with an often authoritarian, supernatural arbiter
who weighed and corrected the imbalances or “injustices” that
erupted in nature. The ancient gods were still worshipped in the
classical era, even after Heraclitus; they had to be exorcised by the
Enlightenment before an ethical continuum between nature and
humanity could be rendered more meaningful and “democratic.”
Late Renaissance thought initiated a new, more rational connection between nature and humanity. Beginning with Galileo and
the new scientific societies that were emerging, the way was
opened to the increasingly democratic participation of everyone
in the discovery of truth. All men — and later women — could now
participate in unearthing knowledge, and the veracity of the facts
they discovered could be judged freely by the merits of their
work, not by their social status.
Today, we may well be able to permit nature — not Dike,
God, Spirit, or an *elan vital* — to open itself up to us as the ground
for an ethics on its own terms. Contemporary science’s greatest
achievement is the growing evidence it provides that randomness
is subject to a directive ordering principle. Mutualism is a good by
virtue of its function in fostering the evolution of natural variety
and complexity. We require no Dike to affirm community as a
desideratum in nature and society. Similarly, the claims of
freedom are validated by what Hans Jonas so perceptively called
the “inwardness” of life-forms, their “organic identity” and “adventure of form.” The effort, venture, indeed self-recognition that
every living being exercises in the course of “its precarious metabolic continuity” to preserve itself reveals — even in the most
rudimentary of organisms — a sense of identity and selective activity that Jonas appropriately called evidence of “germinal
freedom.”[39]
“Open systems,” “minds,” and “holons” may explain the
disequilibria that *change* cybernetic and general systems, but we must
invariably fall back on inherent attributes of substance — notably,
the motion, form, and *sensibilite* of “matter” — to account for the
*development of nature toward complexity, specialization, and consciousness*. This necessity runs counter to every bias on current philosophy, which would ignore the fact of directiveness or endow
it with human traits like *purposiveness* when it is simply a tendency
that inheres in the organization of substance as potentiality.
----
The presuppositions I have made here are not arbitrary. The
validity of a presupposition must be tested against the real *dialectic* of natural development — substance “free and self-moving in
its own peculiar shape” — and not against the “atomies” of data
and statistical probabilities adduced by empirical observation. On
this score at least, contextualists like Whitehead and Bateson are
quite sound in their claim that facts do not exist on their own but
are always relational or *interactive*, to use Diderot’s more germinal
word.
Admittedly, this approach to a nature philosophy may
seem as self-enclosed as the Kantian approach. But I have not
faulted Kantian, neo-Kantian, or for that matter, cybernetic and
positivistic theories for their internal unity or their impregnability
to immanent criticism. My objection to them is their claim to
universality, since their presuppositions provide an inadequate
framework for understanding natural history and apprehending
its ethical implications.
Finally, the study of nature exhibits a self-evolving *nisus*
so to speak, that is *implicitly* ethical. Mutualism, freedom, and
subjectivity are not solely human values or concerns. They appear,
*however germinally*, in larger cosmic or organic processes, but
they require no Aristotelian God to motivate them, no Hegelian
Spirit to vitalize them. If social ecology can provide a coherent
focus on the unity of mutualism, freedom, and subjectivity as
aspects of a cooperative society that is free of domination and
guided by reflection and reason, it will have removed the difficulties that have plagued naturalistic ethics for so long. No longer
would a Cartesian and Kantian dualism leave nature inert and
mind isolated from the world around it. We would see that mind,
far from being sui generis in a world that is wholly external to it,
has a natural history that spans the *sensibilite* of the inorganic and
the conceptual capacities of the human brain. To weaken community, to arrest the spontaneity of a self-organizing reality
toward ever-greater complexity and rationality as nature
rendered self-conscious, would be to deny our heritage in its
evolutionary processes and dissolve our uniqueness in the world
of life.
Mutualism, self-organization, freedom, and subjectivity,
cohered by social ecology’s principles of unity in diversity, spontaneity, and nonhierarchical relationships, are constitutive of
evolution’s potentialities. Aside from the ecological responsibilities they confer on our species as the self-reflexive voice of
nature, they literally define us. Nature does not “exist” for us to
use, but it makes possible our uniqueness. Like the concept of
Being, these principles of social ecology require not analysis but
merely verification. They are the elements of an ethical ontology,
not rules of a game that can be changed to suit personal needs
and interests.
[6] This article was written in September 1982 and published in 1985 in
Michael Tobias, ed., *Deep Ecology* (San Diego, Calif.: Avant Books, 1985). It
has been considerably revised for publication here.
[7] For my distinction between environmentalism and ecology — more
precisely, social ecology — see my “Toward an Ecological Society,” initially
delivered as a lecture at the University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, in the
spring of 1973. It was published as an essay during the same year in *Roots*
and WIN magazines and is now available as the leading essay in the collection of my 1970s writings. *Toward an Ecological Society* (Montreal: Black
Rose Books, 1980).
[8] This phrase is taken, of course, from Max Scheler’s *Man’s Place in Nature*.
[9] Joseph Owens, foreword to Giovanni Reale, *The Concept of First Philosophy and the Unity of “The Metaphysics” of Aristotle* (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1980), p. xv.
[10] See Martin Heidegger, *Early Greek Thinking*, trans. D. F. Krell and F. A.
Capuzzi (New York: Harper and Row, 1975).
[11] See Gregory Vlastos, “Equality and Justice in Early Greek Cosmologies,”
in *Studies in Presocratic Philosophy, vol. 1, The Beginnings of Philosophy*, ed.
David J. Furley and R. E. Allen (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul; New
York: Humanities Press, 1970), pp. 56–91.
[12] Lawrence J. Henderson, *The Fitness of the Environment* (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1958), pp. 1, 5.
[13] Vlastos, “Equality and Justice,” p. 60. Heraclitus, the least democratic of
the Presocratics, does not speak of *isonomia* but of the “One,” which we
can properly distinguish from the “Whole.” This mystical thrust already
prefigures neo-Platonism, which would emphasize the transcendental
and the socially elitist elements in Greek philosophy.
[14] F. M. Cornford, *From Religion to Philosophy: A Study in the Origins of Western Speculation* (1912; New York: Harper and Row, 1957), p. 64.
[15] Ibid., p. 84.
[16] Ibid., p. 85.
[17] Karl Jaspers, *Kant*, trans. Ralph Manheim (New York: Harcourt, Brace and
World, 1962), pp. 50, 51.
[18] A Kantian philosophy of subjectivity is certainly inadequate for social
theory. To call for “intersubjectivity,” for example, as in Jurgen
Habermas’s “ideal speech situation,” without specifying what kind of
political institutions are needed to give that “intersubjectivity” rational
form, tells us little about the role of “intersubjectivity” in social relations.
That Habermas himself, at this writing (1994), has turned to social
democracy as the best route to social rationality is evidence of the
waywardness of “intersubjectivity” as a conceptual basis for social
theory, analysis, and reconstruction.
[19] G.W.F. Hegel, *The Philosophy of Mind*, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: The
Clarendon Press, 1971), p. 315.
[20] Gregory Bateson, *Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity* (New York: E. P
Dutton, 1979), p. 11.
[21] Ibid., pp. 31, 93.
[22] Arthur Koestler, *Janus: A Summing Up* (New York: Random House, 1978).
[23] I have explored the mechanistic aspects of cybernetics and systems
theory in “Energy, ‘Ecotechnology, and Ecology,” in my *Toward an Ecological Society* (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1980).
[24] Morris Berman, an admirer of Bateson’s work, has carefully explored the
highly authoritarian character of Bateson’s social outlook in
*The Reenchantment of the World* (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1981),
pp. 280–96. I disagree with Berman’s view, however, that an anarchic
ecological society follows from Bateson’s cybernetic approach.
[25] Koesder, *Janus*, pp. 30–34. Koestler tries to rescue the word *hierarchy* as an
expression of “flexibility and freedom” in counterposition to reductionism, even as the term *hierarchy* haunts him because “it is loaded with
military and ecclesiastical associations ... [and] conveys the impression of
a rigid, authoritarian structure.” I will certainly not dispute this latter
view.
[26] Bateson, *Mind and Nature*, p. 199.
[27] Ludwig von Bertalanffy, *Robots, Men and Minds: Psychology in the Modern World* (New York: Braziller, 1967), p, 9.
[28] Ibid., pp. 69,71.
[29] Gregoire Nicolis and Ilya Prigogine, *Self-Organization in Nonequilibrium Systems* (New York: John Wiley, 1977). For more on Prigoginian systems
theory, see my essay “Thinking Ecologically,” elsewhere in this book.
[30] By far the best English translation of Diderotis works is Jean Stewart and
Jonathan Kemp’s *Diderot: Interpreter of Nature: Selected Writings* (New
York: International Publishers, 1936), which captures the elegance and
rich nuance of Diderot’s prose that are often lost in English translations.
[31] G.W.F. Hegel, *Phenomenology of Spirit*, trans. A. V Miller (Oxford: The
Clarendon Press, 1977), p. 49.
[32] Friedrich Engels, *Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy*, in
Marx and Engels, *Selected Works*, vol. 2, p. 330; quoted in Georg Lukács,
*The Young Hegel: Studies in the Relations between Dialectics and Economics*,
trans. Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press; London: The
Merlin Press, 1975), p. 468.
[33] See Erwin Schrodinger, *What is Life? Mind and Matter* (Garden City, N.Y.:
Doubleday, 1956). For a more detailed account of the new advances in
astrophysics and biology, see my Vie Ecology of Freedom (1982; Montreal:
Black Rose Books, 1990), from which a number of these passages, generally in modified form, are drawn.
[34] W.illiam Trager, *Symbiosis* (New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold, 1970),
p. vii.
[35] Lynn Margulis, *Symbiosis in Cell Evolution* (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman,
198l). My citation of Margulis applies only to her notion that life played a
role in creating the biosphere. It should not be taken as endorsing either
her reductionist views of prokaryotic cells or her acceptance of the mystical Gaia Hypothesis.
[36] Manfred Eigen, “Molecular Self-Organization and the Early Stages of
Evolution,” *Quarterly Review of Biophysics*, vol. 4 (1971), p. 202.
[37] Margulis, *Symbiosis*, pp. 348–49.
[38] Elizabeth Vrba cited in Robert Lewin, “Evolutionary Theory Under Fire”
*Science*, vol. 210 (1980), pp. 885.
[39] Hans Jonas, *The Phenomenon of Life* (New York: Delta, 1966), pp. 82, 90.
** Freedom and Necessity in Nature:
A Problem in Ecological Ethics[40]
One of the most entrenched ideas in Western thought is the notion
that nature is a harsh realm of necessity, a domain of unrelenting
lawfulness and compulsion. From this underlying idea, two extreme attitudes have emerged. Either humanity must yield with
religious or “ecological” humility to the dicta of “natural law” and
take its abject place side by side with the lowly ants on which it
“arrogantly” treads, *or* it must “conquer” nature by means of its
technological and rational astuteness, in a shared project ultimately to “liberate” all of humanity from the compulsion of natural
“necessity” — an enterprise that may well entail the subjugation of
human by human.
The first attitude, a quasi-religious quietism, is typified by
“deep ecology,” antihumanism, and sociobiology, while the
second, an activist approach, is typified by the liberal and
Marxian image of an omniscient humanity cast in a commandeering
posture toward the natural world. Modern science — despite its
claims to value-free objectivity — unwittingly takes on an ethical
mantle when it commits itself to a concept of nature as
comprehensible, as orderly in the sense that nature’s “laws” are
rationally explicable and basically necessitarian.
The ancient Greeks viewed this orderly structure of the
natural world as evidence of a cosmic *nous* or *logos* that produced
a subjective presence in natural phenomena as a whole. Yet with
only a minimal shift in emphasis, this same notion of an orderly
nature can yield the dismal conclusion that “freedom is the recognition of necessity” (to use Friedrich Engels’s rephrasing of
Hegel’s definition). In this latter case, freedom is subtly turned
into its opposite: the mere *consciousness* of what we can or cannot
do.
Such an internalized view of freedom as subject to higher
dicta, of “Spirit” (Hegel) or “History” (Marx), not only served
Luther in his break with the Church’s hierarchy; it provided an
ideological justification for Stalin’s worst excesses in the name of
dialectical materialism and his brutal industrialization of Russia
under the aegis of society’s “natural laws of development.” It may
also yield an outright Skinnerian notion of an overly determined
world in which human behavior is reduced to mere responses to
external or internal stimuli.
These extremes aside, the conventional wisdom of our
time still sees nature as a harsh “realm of necessity” — morally, as
well as materially — that constitutes a challenge to humanity’s
survival and well-being, not to speak of its freedom. With the
‘considerable intellectual heritage of dystopian thinkers like Hobbes
and utopian ones like Marx, the self-definition of major academic
disciplines embodies this tension, indeed, this conflict.
Economics was forged in the crucible of a necessitarian, even
“stingy” nature whose “scarce resources” were thought to be
insufficient to meet humanity’s “unlimited needs.” Psychology,
certainly inks_psychoanalytic forms, stresses the importance of
controlling human internal nature, with the bonus that the
individual’s sublimated energy will find its expression in the
subjugation of external nature. Theories of work,, society, behavior,
and even sexuality turn on an image of a necessitarian nature,
that must in some sense be “dominated” to serve human ends —
presumably on the old belief that what is natural disallows *all*
elements of choice and freedom. Nor is nature philosophy itself
untainted by this harshly necessitarian image. Indeed, more
often than not, it has served as an ideological justification for a
hierarchical society, modeled on a hierarchically structured
“natural order.”
This image and its social implications, generally associated
with Aristotle, still live in our midst as a cosmic justification for
domination in general — in its more noxious cases, for racial and
sexual discrimination, and in its most nightmarish form, for the
outright extermination of entire peoples. Raised to a moral
calling, “man” emerges from this massive ideological apparatus as a
creature to whom “Spirit” or “God” has imparted a supranatural
quality of a transcendental kind and a mission to govern an
ordered universe that “He” or “It” created.
----
At first glance, resolving the conflict between necessity and
freedom — presumably between nature and society — seems to
require building a bridge between the two, as in value systems that
are based on purely utilitarian attitudes toward the natural
world. The argument that humanity’s abuse of nature subverts
the material conditions for our own survival, although surely
true, is nonetheless crassly instrumental. It assumes that human
concern for nature rests on self-interest rather than on a feeling
for the living world of which human beings are part, albeit in a
very distinctive way. In such a value system our relationship with
nature is neither better nor worse than the success with which we
plunder it without harming ourselves. It is another warrant for
undermining the natural world, provided only that we can find
adequate substitutes, however synthetic, simple, or mechanical,
for existing life-forms and ecological relationships. It is precisely
this approach that has exacerbated the present ecological crisis”?
Moreover, attempts to bridge the gulf between the natural
and social worlds that are premised on a mechanical dualism between nature and society can indirectly preserve this dualism
even as they seek to overcome it. This kind of purely *structural* approach has given rise to splits between body and mind, reality
and thought, object and subject, country and town, and ultimately, society and the individual. It is not far-fetched to say that the
primary schism between nature and humanity has nourished a
wide variety of splits in everyday life as well as in our theoretical
sensibilities.
No less serious a fallacy is to attempt to overcome these
dualisms simply by reducing one element of the duality to the
other or, seriously, to attempt to dissolve humanity into nature.
The universal “night in which all cows are black,” as Hegel
phrased it in his *Phenomenology of Spirit*, attains unity by sacrificing the variety and the uniqueness of humanity as a remarkable
product of natural evolution. Such reductionism yields a crude
mechanistic spiritualism that is merely the counterpart of the
prevailing mechanistic materialism. In either case, a nuanced interpretation of evolutionary phenomena that takes into account
distinctions and gradations as well as continuities is replaced by a
simplistic dualism that dismisses the phases that enter into any
process. It embraces a simplistic and mystical “Oneness” that
overrides the immense wealth of differentiae to which the
present biosphere is heir — the rich, fecund constituents that make
up our evolution and that are preserved in nearly all existing
phenomena.
It is surprising that ecology, one of the most organic of
contemporary disciplines, is itself so lacking in organic ways of
thinking — that is, in forms of reason that inwardly derive, or
educe, differentiae from one another, the full from the germinal,
the complex from the simple — in short, in thinking organically
and eductively, not merely deducing conclusions from hypotheses in typical mathematical fashion, or simply tabulating and
classifying facts. Ecologists too often share with accountants the
mode of reasoning so prevalent today, one that is largely analytical and classificatory rather than processual and developmental.
Appropriate as analytical, classificatory, and deductive modes of
reasoning are for assembling automobile engines or constructing
buildings, they are woefully inadequate for ascertaining the
phases that make up a process, each with its own integrity yet as
part of an ever-developing continuum. We may well fail to understand life itself if we see life-forms as little more than factors
in production, as “natural resources” to be placed in the service
of wealth, rather than as part of the creative phenomenon of life.
Again, this mechanistic sensibility and its analytic mode of
thought is alien to processual thought, to apprehending
development and its phases — both their differences and their
continuities.
It is becoming a cliche to fault humanity’s “separation”
from nature as the source of “alienation” in our highly fragmented
world. We must see that *every* process is also a form of alienation,
in the sense that differentiation involves separation from older
forms of being as well as the absorption of what is negated into
the new, such that the whole is the richly varied fulfillment of its
latent potentialities. Standing in marked contrast to this view of
alienation as self-expression or self-articulation as well as opposition is an all-pervasive epistemology of rule that sorts difference
as such (indeed, the “other” in all its forms) into an ensemble of
antagonistic relationships structured around command and
obedience. That the “other” is at least part of a whole, however differentiated it is, eludes the modern mind in a flux of experience
that knows division exclusively as conflict or breakdown.[41]
The real world is indeed divided antagonistically, to be
remedied by struggle, reconciliation — and transcendence. But if
the thrust of evolution has any meaning, it is that a continuum is
processual precisely in that it is graded as well as united, a flow of
derived phases as well as a shared development from the simpler
to the more complex. Neither conflict nor differentiation should
be permitted to override the other as the long-range character of
development in nature and society.
----
What then does it mean to speak of complexity, variety, and
unity-in-diversity in developmental processes? Ecologists generally treat diversity as a source of ecological stability, in the belief
that while the vulnerability to pests of a single crop treated with
pesticides can reach alarming proportions, a more diversified
crop, in which a number of plant and animal species interact,
produces natural checks on pest populations.[42]
But the fact that biotic — and social — evolution has been
marked until recently by the development of ever more complex
species and ecocommunities raises an even more challenging
issue. The diversity of an ecocommunity may be a source of
greater stability from an agricultural standpoint; but from an
evolutionary standpoint, it may be an ever-expanding, albeit nascent source of freedom within nature, a medium for providing
varying degrees of *choice, self-directiveness, and participation by life-forms in their own development*.
I wish to propose that the evolution of living beings is no
mere passive process, the product of exclusively chance conjunctions between random genetic changes and “selective” environmental “forces,” and that the “origin of species” is no mere result
of external influences that determine the “fitness” of a life-form to
“survive” as a result of random factors in which life is simply an
“object” of an indeterminable “selective” process. The increase in
diversity in the biosphere *opens new evolutionary pathways*, indeed,
alternative evolutionary directions, in which species play an active role in their own survival and change. However nascent,
choice is not totally absent from biotic evolution; indeed, it increases as species become structurally, physiologically, and above
all neurologically more complex. As the ecological contexts
within which species evolve — the communities and interactions
they form — become more complex, they open new avenues for
evolution and a greater ability of life-forms to act self-selectively,
forming the bases for some kind of choice, favoring precisely
those species that can participate in ever-greater degrees in their
own evolution, basically in the direction of greater complexity. Indeed, species and the ecocommunities in which they interact to
create more complex forms of evolutionary development are increasingly the very “forces” that account for evolution as a whole.
“Participatory evolution,” as I call this view, is somewhat at
odds with the prevalent Darwinian or neo-Darwinian syntheses,
in which nonhuman life-forms are primarily “objects” of selective
forces exogenous to them. No less is it at odds with Henri
Bergson’s “creative evolution,” with its semimystical *elan vital*.
Ecologists, like biologists, have yet to come to terms with the notion that symbiosis (not only “struggle”) and participation (not
only “competition”) factor in the evolution of species. The
prevalent view of nature still stresses the exclusively “necessitarian” character of the natural world. An immense literature,
both, artistic and scientific, stresses the “cruelty” of a nature that
bears no witness to the suffering of life and that is “indifferent” to
cries of pain in the “struggle for existence.” “Cruel” nature, in this
imagery, offers no solace for extinction — merely an all-embracing
darkness of meaningless motion to which humanity can oppose
only the light of its culture and mind. Such formulations impart a
sophisticated ethical dimension to the natural world that is more
anthropomorphic than meaningful.
But even if the formulation is anthroppmorphic, it bespeaks a presence in natural evolution — subjectivity and specifically *human* consciousness — that cannot be ignored in formulating an evolutionary theory. We may reasonably claim that
human will and freedom, at least as self-consciousness and selfreflection, have their own natural history in potentialities of the
natural world — in contrast to the view that they are sui generis,
the product of a rupture with the whole of development so unprecedented and unique that it contradicts the gradedness of all
phenomena from the antecedent potentialities that lie behind and
within every processual “product.” Such claims are intended to
underwrite our efforts to deal with the natural world as we
choose — indeed, as Marx put it in the *Grundrisse*, to regard nature
merely as “an object for mankind, purely a matter of utility.”
The dim choices that animals exercise in their own evolution should not be confused with the will and degree of intentionality that human beings exhibit in their social lives. Nor is the
nascent freedom that is rendered possible by natural complexity
cqmparable to the ability of humans to make rational decisions.
The differences between the two are qualitative, however much
they can be traced back to the evolution of all animals.
Our tendency to ignore the close interaction between
evolving life-forms and the environmental forces that “select”
them for survival is a mechanistic prejudice that still clings to
evolutionary theory. All anti-Cartesian protestations to the contrary, we still view nonhuman life-forms as little more than
machines or inert beings. Structurally, we may fill them out with
protoplasm, but operationally we impute no more meaning to
them than to mechanical devices — a judgment, it is worth noting,
that is not without economic utility in dealing with working
people as “hands” or “operatives.”
Despite the monumental nature of his work, Darwin did
not fully organicize evolutionary theory. He brought a profound
evolutionary sensibility to the “origin of species,” but in the
minds of his acolytes species still stood somewhere between inorganic machines and mechanically functioning organisms. No less
significant are the empirical origins of Darwin’s own work,
which are deeply rooted in the Lockean atomism that nourished
nineteenth-century British science as a whole. Allowing for the
nuances that appear in all great books, *The Origin of Species* accounts for the way in which *individual* species originate, evolve,
adapt, survive, change, or pay the penalty of extinction as if they
were fairly isolated from their environment. In that account, any
one species stands for the world of life as a whole, in isolation
from the life-forms that normally interact with it and with which
it is interdependent. Although predators depend upon their prey,
to be sure, Darwin portrays the strand from ancestor to descendant in lofty isolation, such that early *eohippus* rises, step by step,
from its plebeian estate to attain the aristocratic grandeur of a
sleek race horse. The paleontological diagramming of bones from
former “missing links” to the culminating beauty of *Equus caballus*
more closely resembles the adaptation of Robinson Crusoe from
an English seafarer to a self-sufficient island dweller than the
reality of a truly emerging being.
This reality is contextual in an ecological sense. The horse
lived not only among its predators and food but in creatively interactive relationships with a great variety of plants and animals.
It evolved not alone but in ever-changing ecocommunities, such
that the “rise” of *Equus caballus* occurred conjointly with, that of
other herbivores that shared and maintained their grasslands and
even played a major role in creating them. The string of bones
that traces *eohippus* to *Equus* is evidence of the succession of
ecocommunities in which the ancestral animal and its descendants interacted with other life-forms.
One could more properly modify *The Origin of Species* to
read as the evolution of ecocommunities as well as the evolution
of species.[43] Indeed, placing the community in the foreground of
evolution does not deny the integrity of species, their capacity for
variation, or their unique lines of development. Species become
vital participants in their own evolution — active beings, not
merely passive components — taking full account of their nascent
freedom in the natural process.
Nor are will and reason sui generis. They have their
origins in the growing choices conferred by complexity and in the
alternative pathways opened up by the growth of complex
ecocommunities and the development of increasingly complex
neurological systems — in short, *processes* that are both internal
and external to life-forms. To speak of evolution in very broad
terms tends to conceal the specific evolutionary processes that
make up the overall process. Many anatomical lines of evolution
have occurred: the evolution of the various organs that freed life-forms from their aquatic milieu; of eyes and ears, which sophisticated their awareness of the surrounding environment; and of
the nervous system, from nerve networks to brains. Thus, mind
too has its evolutionary history in the natural world, and as the
neurological capability of life-forms to function more actively and
flexibly increases, so too does life itself help create new evolutionary directions that lead to enhanced self-awareness and selfactivity. Selfhood appears germinally in the communities that
life-forms establish as *active agents in their own evolution*, contrary
to conventional evolutionary theory.
----
Does the nature of evolution warrant introducing a presiding
agent into evolutionary and ecological theory, one that predetermines the development of life-forms along the lines I have
described, a “Spirit,” “God,” “Mind,” or perhaps a semimystical
Bergsonian *elan vital*? I think not, if only because the concept of
such a hidden hand preserves the nature-society dualism itself. So
profoundly does dualism inhere in our mental operations that
when we consider the immanent striving of life-forms toward
various degrees of freedom and self-awareness, we often slip into
explanations involving supernature rather than nature itself,
reductionism rather than differentiation, and succession rather
than culmination. Hence the present revival of the “reverence for
nature” that the nineteenth-century Romantic tradition so poetically cultivated, a “revered” natural world dissolved into a mystical “oneness.”
Not only does this “reverence” preserve and even foster a
nature-society dualism; it restores to evolutionary theory the very
dualism that underpins hierarchy and the view of all differentiation as degrees of domination and subordination. A “revered” nature is a separated nature in the bad sense of the term — that is to
say, a mystified nature. Like the deities that human beings create in
their imagination and worship in temples, mediated by priests and
gurus with their incantations and rituals, this separated nature becomes a reified and contrived phenomenon that is set apart from
the human world, even as human beings genuflect before a mystified “It” “Reverence” for nature, the mythologizing of the natural
world, degrades it by denying nature its universality as that which
exists everywhere, free of dualities like “Spirit” and “God.”
If liberal and Marxist theorists prepared the ideological
bases for plundering the natural world, “biocentrically” oriented
antihumanists and “natural law” devotees may be preparing the
ideological bases for plundering the human spirit. In the course
of “revering nature,” they have created an insidious image of a
humanity whose “intrinsic worth” is no more or less than that of
other species. “Biocentrism” denies humanity its real place in
natural evolution by completely subordinating humanity to the
natural world. Paradoxically, “biocentrism” and antihumanism
also contribute to the alienation and reification of nature such
that a “reverence” for nature can easily be used to negate any existential respect for the diversity of life. Against the background
of a cosmic “Nature,” human life and individuality are completely trivialized, as witness James Lovelock’s description of people as
merely “intelligent fleas” feeding on the body of Gaia. Nor can
we ignore a growing number of “natural law” acolytes who advocate authoritarian measures to control population growth and
forcibly expel urban dwellers from large congested cities, as
though a society that is structured around the domination of
human by human could be expected to leave the natural world
intact.
It is grossly misleading to invoke “biocentrism,” “natural
law,” and antihumanism for ends that deny the most distinctive
of human natural attributes: the ability to reason, to foresee, to
will, and to act insightfully to enhance nature’s own development. In a sense, it deprecates nature to separate these subjective
attributes from it, as though they did not emerge out of evolutionary development and were not implicitly part of animal
development. A humanity that has been rendered oblivious to its
own responsibility to evolution — a responsibility to bring reason
and the human spirit to evolutionary development, to foster
diversity, and to provide ecological guidance such that the harmful and the fortuitous in the natural world are diminished — is a
humanity that *betrays its own evolutionary heritage* and that ignores
its species-distinctiveness and uniqueness.
Ironically, then, a nature that is reverentially hypostatized
is a nature set apart from humanity — and in the very process of
being hypostatized over humanity, it is defamed. A nature
reconstructed into forms apart from itself, however “reverentially,” easily becomes a mere object of utility. Indeed, a revered nature is the converse of the old liberal and Marxian image of
nature “dominated” by man. Both attitudes reinstate the theme of
domination in ecological discussion.
Here the limited form of reasoning based on *deduction*, so
commonplace in conventional logic, supplants an organismic
form of reasoning based on *eduction* — that is, on derivation, so
deeply rooted in the dialectical outlook. *Potentially*, human
reason is an expression of nature rendered self-conscious, a nature that finds its voice in being of its own creation. It is not only
we who must have our own place in nature but nature that
must have its place in us — in an ecological society and in an
ecological ethics based, on humanity’s catalytic role in natural
evolution.
----
Along with the antihumanistic ideologies that foster misanthropic attitudes and actions, the reduction of human beings to
commodities is steadily denaturing and degrading humanity. The
commodification of humanity takes its most pernicious form in
the manipulation of the individual as a means of production and
consumption. Here, human beings are employed (in the literal
sense of the term) as techniques either in production or in consumption, as mere devices whose creative powers and authentic
needs are equally perverted into objectified phenomena. As a
result, we are witnessing today not only the “fetishization of commodities” (to use Marx’s famous formulation) but the fetishization of needs.[44] Human beings are becoming separated from their
own nature as well as from the natural world in an existential
split that threatens to give dramatic reality to Descartes’s theoretical split between the soul and the body. In this sense, the claim
that capitalism is a totally “unnatural order” is only too accurate.
The terrible tragedy of the present social era is not only
that it is polluting the environment; it is also simplifying natural
ecocommunities, social relationships, *and even the human psyche*.
The pulverization of the natural world is being accompanied by
the pulverization of the social and psychological worlds. In this
sense, the conversion of soil into sand in agriculture can be said,
in a metaphorical sense, to apply to society and the human
spirit. The greatest danger we face — apart from nuclear immolation — is the homogenization of the world by a market society
and its objectification of all human relationships and experiences into commodities.
To recover human nature is not only to recover its continuity with the creative process of natural evolution but to
recognize its distinctiveness. To conceive of the participation of
life-forms in evolution is to understand that nature is a realm of
incipient freedom. It is freedom and participation — not simply
necessity — that we must emphasize, an emphasis that involves a
radical break with the conventional image of nature.
Social ecology, in effect, stands at odds with the notion
that culture has no roots whatever in natural evolution. Indeed, it
explores the roots of the cultural in the natural and seeks to ascertain the gradations of biological development that phase the
natural into the social. By the same token, it also tries to explore
the important differences that distinguish the societal from the
natural and to ascertain the gradations of social development
that, hopefully, will yield a new, humanistic ecological society.
The two lines of exploration go together in producing a larger
whole, indeed, one that must transcend even the *present*
capitalist society based on perpetual growth and profit. To identify society as such with the present society, to see in capitalism an
“emancipatory” movement precisely because it frees us from nature, is not only to ignore the roots of society in nature but to
identify a perverted society with humanism and thereby to give
credence to the antihumanist trends in ecological thinking.
This much is clear: the way we view our position in the
natural world is deeply entangled with the way we organize the
social world. In large part, the former derives from the latter and
serves, in turn, to reinforce social ideology. Every society projects
its own perception of itself onto nature, whether as a tribal cosmos that is rooted in kinship communities, a feudal cosmos that
originates in and underpins a strict hierarchy of rights and duties,
a bourgeois cosmos structured around a market society that
fosters human rivalry and competition, or a corporate cosmos
diagrammed in flow charts, feedback systems, and hierarchies
that mirror the operational systems of modern corporate society.
That some of these images reveal a truthful aspect of nature,
whether as a community or a cybernetic flow of energy, does not
justify the universal, almost imperialistic claims that their
proponents stake out for them over the world as a whole. Ultimately, only a society that has come into its “truth” to use
Hegelian language — a rational and ecological society — can free
us from the limits that oppressive and hierarchical societies impose on our understanding of nature.
The power of social ecology lies in the association it establishes between society and ecology, in understanding that the social is, potentially at least, a fulfillment of the *latent* dimension of
freedom in nature, and that the ecological is a major organizing
principle of social development. In short, social ecology advances
the guidelines for an ecological society. The great divorce between nature and society — or between the “biological” and the
“cultural” — is overcome by shared developmental concepts such
as greater diversity in evolution; the wider and more complete
participation of all components in a whole; and the ever more
fecund potentialities that expand the horizon of freedom and self-reflexivity. Society, like mind, ceases to be sui generis. Like mind,
with its natural history, social life emerges from the loosely
banded animal community to form the highly institutionalized
human community.[45]
Social ecology challenges the image of an unmediated
natural evolution, in which the human mind, society, and even culture are sui generis, in which nonhuman nature is irretrievably
separated from human nature, and in which an ethically defamed
nature finds no expression whatever in society, mind, and human
will. It seeks to throw a critical and meaningful light on the phased,
graded, and cumulative development of nature into society, richly
mediated by the prolonged dependence of the human young on
parental care, by the blood tie as the earliest social and cultural
bond beyond immediate parental care, by the so-called “sexual
division of labor,” and by age-based status groups and their role in
the origin of hierarchy.
Ultimately, it is the institutionalization of the human community that distinguishes society from the nonhuman community — whether for the worse, as in the case of pre-1789 France
or tsarist Russia, where weak, unfeeling tyrants like Louis XVI and
Nicholas H were raised to commanding positions by bureaucracies,
armies, and social classes; or for the better, as in forms of self-governance
and management that empower the people as a whole, like the
Parisian sections during the French Revolution and the anarchosyndicalist collectives during the Spanish Civil War, We see no
such contrived institutional infrastructures in nonhuman communities, although the rudiments of a social bond do exist in the
mother-offspring relationship and in common forms of mutual aid.
With a growing knowledge that sharing, cooperation, and
concern foster healthy human consociation, with the technical
disciplines that open the way for a creative “metabolism” between humanity and nature, and with a host of new insights into
the presence of nature in so much of our own civilization, it can
no longer be denied that nature is still with us. Indeed, it has
returned to us ideologically as a challenge to the devouring of
“natural resources” for profit and the mindless simplification of
the biosphere. We can no longer speak meaningfully of a “new”
or “rational” society without also tailoring our social relationships
and institutions to the ecocommunities in which our social communities are located. In short, any rational future society must be
an ecological society, conjoining humanity’s capacity for innovation, technological development, and intellectuality with the nonhuman natural world on which civilization itself rests and human
well-being depends.
The ecological principles that enter into biotic evolution
do not disappear from social evolution, any more than the
natural history of mind can be dissolved into Kant’s ahistorical
epistemology. Quite the contrary: the societal and cultural are
ecologically derivative, as the men’s and women’s houses in
tribal communities so clearly illustrate. The relationship between nature and society is a cumulative one, while each
remains distinctive and creative in its own right. Perhaps most
significant, the nature of which the societal and cultural are
derivative — and cumulative — is a nature that is a potential
realm of freedom and subjectivity, and humanity is potentially
the most self-conscious and self-reflexive expression of that
natural development.
----
Social ecology, by definition, takes on the responsibility of evoking, elaborating, and giving an ethical content to the natural
core of society and humanity.[46] Granting the limitations that
society imposes on our thinking, the development of mind out
of “first nature” produces an objective ground for an ethics, indeed, for formulating a vision of a rational society that is neither
hierarchical nor relativistic: an ethics that is based neither on
atavistic appeals to “blood and soil” and inexorable “social laws”
(“dialectical” or “scientific”) on the one hand, nor on the
wayward consensus of public opinion polls, which will support
capital punishment one year and life imprisonment the next.
Freedom becomes a desideratum as self-reflexivity, as self-management, and most excitingly, as a creative and active
process that, with its *ever-expanding horizon*, resists the moral imperatives of a rigid definition and the jargon of temporally conditioned biases.[47]
An ecological ethics of freedom would provide an objective directiveness to the human enterprise. We have no need to
degrade nature or society into a crude biologism at one extreme
or a crude dualism at the other. A diversity that nurtures
freedom, an interactivity that enhances complementarity, a
wholeness that fosters creativity, a community that strengthens
individuality, a growing subjectivity that yields greater
rationality — all are desiderata that provide the ground for an objective ethics. They are also the real principles of any graded
evolution, one that renders not only the past explicable but the
future meaningful.
An ecological ethics of freedom cannot be divorced from a
technics that enhances our relationship with nature — a creative,
not destructive, “metabolism” with nature. Human beings must
be active agents in the biosphere — vividly, expressively, and rationally — not retreat into the passive animism of pagan, Taoist,
and Buddhist mystics who recycle Asian philosophies and sensibilities through the ashrams and religious temples of the Pacific
rim of the United States. But it makes all the difference in the
world if we cultivate food not only on behalf of our physical wellbeing but with regard for the well-being of the soil as well. Inasmuch as agriculture is always a culture, the differences in the
methods and intentions involved are no less cultural than a book
on engineering. Yet in the first case, our intentions are informed
by economic considerations at best and greed at worst; in the
second, by an ecological sensibility. Society must recover the plasticity of the organic in the sense that every dimension of experience must be infused with an ecological, a *dialectical*
sensibility. There is a profoundly ethical dimension to the attempt
to bring soil, flora, and fauna (or what we neatly call the food
chain) into our lives, not only as “wholesome” sources of food but
as part of a broad movement in which consumption is no less a
creative process than production — originating in the soil and
returning to it in a richer form all the components that make up
the food cycle.
So, too, in the production of objects it makes all the difference in the world if craftspeople work with a respect for their
materials, emphasizing quality and artistry in production rather
than mass-producing commodities with no concern for handling
materials sparingly, let alone for human needs. In the former,
production and consumption go beyond the pure economic
domain of the buyer-seller relationship, indeed, beyond the
domain of mere material sustenance, and enter into the ecological
domain as a mode of enhancing the fecundity of an eco-community. An ecotechnology — for consumption no less than
production — serves to enrich an ecosystem just as compost in
food cultivation enriches the soil, rather than degrading and
simplifying the natural fundament of life. An ecotechnology is
thus a moral technology, a technology that stands at odds with
gigantism, waste, and the mass destruction wrought on the environment by capitalistic forms of technology designed purely for profit.
The choices we make in these respects — in the food we
grow and eat, in the objects we produce and consume — are between an ecological alternative and a purely economic one. We
are profoundly influenced by social institutions, whichever alternative we choose. In the end, our choice will be between an
ecocommunity or a market community, between a society infused
by life or a society infused by gain. Yet no rational society can
hope to exist, still less stabilize itself, without amply meeting
human needs and providing the free time to create a fully
democratic polity. The advances in technology that mark the past
few centuries cannot be dismissed exclusively because of the
damage they have inflicted both on the natural world and on the
human condition. For now we can at least *choose* the kind of
world in which we want to live — we can choose to bring science
and technological knowledge to the service of humanity and the
biosphere alike.
To say that nature belongs in humanity just as humanity
belongs in nature is to express a highly reciprocal and complementary relationship between the two instead of one structured around subordination and domination. Neither society nor
nature dissolves into the other. Rather, social ecology tries to
recover the distinctive attributes of both in a continuum that
gives rise to a substantive ethics, wedding the social to the
ecological without denying the integrity of each.
----
The fecundity and potentiality for freedom that variety and complexity bring to natural evolution, indeed, that emerge from
natural evolution, can also be said in a qualitatively advanced
form to apply to social evolution and psychic development. The
more diversified a society and its psychic life, the more creative it
is, and the greater the opportunity for freedom it is likely to
offer — not only in terms of new choices that open up to human
beings but also in terms of the richer social background that
diversity and complexity create. As in natural evolution, so too in
social evolution we must go beyond the image that diversity and
complexity yield greater stability — the usual claim that ecologists
make for the two — and emphasize that they yield greater
creativity, choices, and freedom.
At the same time there can be no return to the past — to the
domestic realm, to the age-ranks, or to the kinship relationships
of tribalism. Nor can there be a return to the myths, amulets,
magical practices, and idols — female or male — of the past. While
we redeem what is valuable in premodern societies for enhancing
human solidarity and an ecological sensibility, we must also
transcend all the parochial and divisive features of the past and
present. If we are to create a truly rational and ecological society,
we must nourish the insights provided by reason to create a sense
of a shared humanity that is bound neither by gendered outlooks
nor by beliefs in deities — all of which, ironically, are merely
anthropomorphic projections of our own beings and sensibilities
(as Ludwig Feuerbach so clearly saw) — and we must commit ourselves to a belief in the potentialities of humanity to foresee and
understand, to be the embodiment of mind.
No ecological ethics of freedom can be divorced from a
politics of participation, a politics that fosters self-empowerment
rather than state empowerment. Such a politics must become a
truly peopled politics in the sense that political participation is
literally peopled by assemblies and by face-to-face discussion.
The political ethics that follows from this ground is meant to create an ethical community, not simply an “efficient” one; an
ecological community, not simply an environmentally “hygienic”
one; a social and political praxis that yields freedom, not a statist
culture that merely allows a measure of public assent.
If history is a bloody “slaughterbench,” the blood that
covers it is not only that of civilization’s innocent victims but that
of the angry men and women who have left us a legacy of
freedom. The legacy of freedom and the legacy of domination
have often been tragically intermingled. If we are to rescue ourselves from the homogenizing effects of a market society, it is
necessary that humanity’s waning memory of heroic struggles to
achieve freedom be rescued from this society’s pollution — a
process that has already gone far in contemporary culture.
[40] This article was originally published in *Alternatives*, vol. 13, no. 4
(November 1986). It has been significantly revised for publication here.
[41] Despite some recent nonsense to the effect that the Frankfurt School
reconnoitered a nonhierarchical and ecological view of society’s future,
in no sense were its ablest thinkers, Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno,
resolutely critical of hierarchy and domination. Rather, their views
were clearly pessimistic: reason and civilization, for better or worse,
entail “uncompromising individuals [who] may have been in favor of unity
and cooperation ... to build a strong hierarchy.... The history of the old
religions and schools like that of the modern parties and revolutions
teaches us that the price for survival is practical involvement, the transformation of ideas into domination.” See Horkheimer and Adorno,
*Dialectic of Enlightenment* (New York: Herder and Herder, 1972; originally
published in 1944), pp. 213, 215. The power of these thinkers lay in their
opposition to positivism and the theoretical problems they raised, not in
the solutions they offered. Attempts to make them into proto-social
ecologists, much less precursors of bioregionalism, involve a gross
misreading of their ideas or, worse, a failure to read their works at all.
[42] This approach was still rather new some twenty-five years ago, when I
pioneered it together with rare colleagues like Charles S. Elton. Today it
has become commonplace in ecological and environmental thinking, as
have organic methods of gardening.
[43] Darwin did not deny the role of animal interactivity in evolution,
particularly in the famous Chapter 3 of *The Origin of Species*, where he
suggests that “ever-increasing circles of complexity” check populations that,
left uncontrolled, would reach pest proportions. But he sees this as a
“battle within battles [which] must be continually recurring with varying
success” (on p. 58 of the Modern Library edition). Moreover, “the
dependency of one organic being on another” — typically “as of a parasite
on its prey” — is secondary to the struggle “between individuals of the
same species” (p. 60). Like most Victorians, Darwin had a strongly
providential and moral side to his character: “we may console ourselves,”
he assures us, “that the war of nature is generally prompt, and that the
vigorous, the healthy, and the happy survive and multiply” (p. 62).
Indeed: “How fleeting are the wishes and efforts of man! how short his
time! and consequently how poor will be his results, compared with
those accumulated by Nature’s productions during whole geological
periods! Can we wonder, then, that Nature’s productions should be far
‘truer’ than man’s productions; that they should be infinitely better
adapted to the most complex conditions of life, and should plainly bear
the stamp of a far higher workmanship?” (p. 66). These remarks do not
make Darwin an ecologist but are marvelous asides to a thesis that
emphasizes variation, selection, fitness, and above all struggle. Yet one
cannot help but be entranced by a moral sensibility that would have been
magnificently responsive to the message of modern ecology and that
deserves none of the onerous rubbish that has been imputed to the man
because of social Darwinism.
[44] See Murray Bookchin, *The Ecology of Freedom* (Palo Alto: Cheshire Books,
1982; Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1991), pp. 68–69.
[45] An ecological approach can spare us some of the worst absurdities of
sociobiology and biological reductionism. The popular notion that our
deep-seated “reptilian” brain is responsible for our aggressive, “brutish,”
and cruel behavioral traits may make for good television dramas like
*Cosmos*, but it is ridiculous science. Like all the great animal groups, most
Mesozoic reptiles were almost certainly gentle herbivores, not
carnivores — and those that were carnivores were probably neither more nor
less aggressive, “brutish,” or “cruel” than mammals. Our images of
Tyrannosaurus rex (a creature whose generic name is sociological
nonsense) may be inordinately frightening, but they grossly distort the
reptilian life-forms on which the carnivore preyed. If anything, the majority
of Mesozoic reptiles were probably very pacific and easily frightened, all
the more because they were not particularly intelligent vertebrates. What
remains unacknowledged in this imagery of fierce, fire-breathing, and
“unfeelingly cruel” reptiles is the implicit assumption of different psychic
sensibilities in reptiles and mammals, the latter presumably being more
“sensitive” and “understanding” than the former. A psychic evolution in
nonhuman beings thus goes together with the evolution of intelligence.
Yet confronted with the unstated premises of such evolutionary trends,
few scientists would find them comfortable.
[46] This project is elaborated in considerable detail in my book
*The Ecology of Freedom.*
[47] Hence freedom is no longer resolvable into a strident nihilistic negativity
or a trite instrumental positivity. Rather, in its open-endedness, it
contains both and transcends them as a continuing process. Freedom thus
resists precise definition just as it resists terminal finality. It is always
becoming, hopefully surpassing what it was in the past and developing into
what it can be in the future.
** Thinking Ecologically:
A Dialectical Approach [48]
In a time of sweeping social breakdown and intellectual fragmentation, it is not surprising to find that patchwork eclecticism and
ideological faddism are seriously corroding the very notion of
coherent thinking. Although such ideological deterioration has
occurred in earlier periods of social decay, one might have hoped
that ecological thinking — with its emphasis on the organic, the
holistic, and the developmental — would have provided an
ideological terrain from which we could resist the general fragmentation of our times. Tragically, this hope has not been fulfilled.
Many contemporary ecophilosophies, in fact, far from countering
the trend toward eclecticism and faddism, seem to be reinforcing
it Indeed, we are being overwhelmed by an effluvium of fads
prefixed by eco- that pander to New Age pop styles. Too often,
these “eco”-faddists either ignore muscularity of thought as too
“heavy,” or else they condemn it as intellectually “linear” and
“divisive.” As a result, a mentally lazy readership is emerging that
is startled by serious thought that is in any way demanding — and
even “turned off” by it (to use “counterculture” jargon).
More specifically, Taoist moods, Buddhist homilies, and
New Age platitudes seem to be replacing even genuine thinking, let alone the possibility of organic reasoning that social
ecology raised a decade or so ago. As simplified interpretations
of Eastern thought — light-mindedly mixed with Heideggerian
“woodpaths” and Jungian archetypes — obscure the many gnawing philosophical problems that are endemic to ecological
thought, surprisingly few ecologically oriented people seem to
feel that Western philosophy and social theory have much to
contribute. Instead, the Western tradition is reviled as the
monolithic source of ecological problems. Indeed, it is stylish to
heap epithets on Descartes as the “source” of dualism and on
Francis Bacon as the “source” of scientism — with or without
reading their works. But rich traditions of ideas that originated
in ancient Athens, that reached their high point in thinkers like
Denis Diderot and particularly Hegel, and that still haunt us in
the works of R. G. Collingwood and Hans Jonas, are ignored.
(Need I add that social theory suffers even more, especially from
a lack of in-depth study of Rousseau, Marx, and Kropotkin.) Nor
is Western thought made artificially relevant to ecological thinking by turning Spinoza into a Buddhist — a kind of “woodpath”
that was first cleared years ago, when Erich Fromm tried to turn
Marx into a Zen master. To orientalize — California style — thinkers
whose work emerged from distinctly Western problematics and
traditions not only violates Western traditions and their integrity but serves to obscure both the contributions and the failings of these thinkers, thereby distorting them.
What is especially important is that the Western organismic tradition is much sturdier in its thrust than the Eastern. All
too often, what “eco”-faddists unknowingly take from the West is
not its organismic tradition but, ironically, its static analytical
positivistic logic, a way of reasoning that stands at odds with organismic tendencies — even as they turn to the East for poetry to
satisfy their more spiritualistic proclivities. This oddly schizophrenic ideological mutation has produced a strange twist in
philosophical thinking within today’s ecology movement: even
as its mind is Western in its harsh instrumental methodology, its
heart is uncritically Eastern in its sentimentality. The strange
combination of a Western “mind,” in its most instrumental and
analytical positivistic form, with an Eastern “heart,” at its most
vaporous and squamous, cannot be resolved by a gospel of peaceable coexistence but must ultimately yield a total contradiction.
Ecology’s “pop” culture is at war with its own logical underpinnings.
Today’s eclecticism jumbles together thinkers whose ideas
are, to say the least, unrelated. In the academy, an incoherent
body of “ecophilosophy” has emerged — a catchall “receptacle”
(to borrow a metaphor from Plato’s *Timaeus*) that wildly mixes
tendencies that are sharply at variance with each other logically
but that coexist in a blissful state of ignorance emotionally. To roll
together Heidegger’s ineffable “openness to Being” and Barry
Commoner’s trite cafeteria “ecology,” with its maxim that there is
“no such thing as a free lunch” in nature, is adolescent at best
and insidious at worst It asks us to descend from the Bavarian
Alps to a New Jersey shopping mall without even popping an
eardrum.
Typical of this eclecticism is “deep ecology” — widely discussed at ecological conferences these days, even as participants
contemplate what is “deeper” than “deep ecology.” Yet its very
name typifies a confusion in semantics. Leaving aside the problems
of using the dimensional word *deep*, “shallow ecology” — intended
as the technocratic counterpart of “deep ecology” — is hardly to be
graced with the word *ecology* when it is in fact nothing more than
*environmentalism*. Moreover, one can be very “deep” but profoundly wrong, as Cartesian philosophy and positivist theory reveal
today It does not help one’s ecology — whether deep, shallow, or
social — to fill in its gaps with some plaster borrowed from Taoism,
mortar from Buddhism, concrete from Heidegger, and bricks from
Spinoza, not to speak of mud from Commoner, Paul Ehrlich, and
the like. Attempts to compost a great variety of views under a common rubric like “deep ecology” or “bioregionalism” are gravely
misleading: there are differences within the ecology movement
that are utterly at odds with each other, and their divergences are
more important than their so-called “common goal”.
There is, in fact, an organismic tradition in Western
thought that is at least as rich as that of the East. Moreover,
longstanding debates in the Western tradition have engaged
philosophers with highly important problems that the East has
not confronted as fully; indeed, the Western organismic tradition
is much sturdier in its thrust than the Eastern. One does not have
to travel far into Eastern thought to find dualisms that are no less
intractable than Descartes’s and notions of dominating nature
that are no less strident than Bacon’s. Issues of monism and
dualism, reductionism and dialectic, and the sometimes adversarial relationships between them were articulated, exacerbated,
and confronted more clearly in the West — particularly in the
works of Aristotle, Spinoza, and Hegel — than in the East, where
these notions tended to take a vaporous and mystical form.
If my approach seems too “Eurocentric,” let me warn the
reader that Asian “centricity” is a greater affliction. It is the issues
that ecological thinking raises, rather than geopolitical and
demographic considerations, that should guide us here. Ultimately, the real questions that confront us are not only how to *feel*
ecologically but how to *think* ecologically. The chasm between
thought and feeling is growing wider today, not narrowing,
despite the deluge of orientalized Westernisms that have descended upon us methodologically and the Westernized orientalisms that have descended upon us ontologically. It would be
well, for a moment, to work with one tradition on its own ground
and see what problems it raises and what solutions it advances.
*** Nature philosophy—East and West
To think ecologically is to enter the domain of nature philosophy.
This can be a very perilous step. Serious political ambiguities persist in nature philosophy itself: namely, its potential to nourish
reaction as well as revolution. Contemporary society is still seared
by images of nature that have fostered highly reactionary political
views. Vaporous slogans about “community” and humanity’s
“oneness with nature” easily interplay with the legacy of
“naturalistic” nationalism that reached its genocidal apogee in
Nazism, with its myths of race and “blood and soil.” It requires
only a minor ideological shift from the ideas of the nineteenth-century Romantic movement and William Blake’s mystical anarchism to arrive at Richard Wagner’s mystical nationalism.
Nor does science, for all its claims to objectivity, rescue us
from the waywardness of a nature philosophy tinged with
romanticism and mysticism. The “naturalistic injunctions with
which Hitler initiated his blood-drenched march through Europe
have their counterpart in the cosmic “laws” of natural history
with which Stalin ideologically justified his blood-drenched industrialization of Russia. “Dialectical materialism,” or “diamat” —
which Friedrich Engels restated as “laws” like the “unity of
opposites,” the transformation of “quantity into quality,” and the
“negation of the negation” — anchored social development in an
almost mechanistic causality that was as damning to modern
claims of individuality and freedom as it was to the complex
relationships of society to nature.
It is worth noting that the major theorists of the Frankfurt
School, whose ideas are so fashionable these days, foundered on
the horns of dilemmas that nature philosophy poses. Theodor
Adorno and Max Horkheimer’s dark pessimism about the human
condition stemmed in large part from their inability to anchor an
emancipatory ethics in a radically conceived ecological philosophy. Indeed, reason, in their view, was hopelessly tainted by its
origin (as they understood it) as a means for dominating nature —
a vast, presumably civilizatory enterprise that also required the
domination of human by human as mere instruments of production. Marxist theory justified human servitude and the development of classes as unavoidable steps in humanity’s “tortured”
march toward freedom from material want and hopefully from
social domination itself.[49] Such ideas, which traditional Marxism
and liberalism celebrated and over which the Frankfurt School
brooded, were the received wisdom of the last century. Hence the
inability of so many radical theorists today to grapple with nature
philosophy, dialectic, or indeed, any organic approach that seeks
to reinterpret these outlooks ecologically. The domain of nature
as a ground for freedom has been rendered taboo by the political
consequences of earlier interpretations, many of which have mystified, romanticized, or unified nature and its relationship to
society by means of a cosmic mysticism that preempts reason by
intuition.
On the other hand, the fact that Eastern sages thought
and felt profoundly does not immunize their work to the
criticism that ambiguity clouds much of it. The Tao Te Ching,
imputed to Lao-tzu, can be read not only as the peasantry’s “way”
for moving with the “grain” of nature but as a handbook for
elitist control of the peasantry — an ambiguity that is no less
troubling than the fact that Plato’s *Republic* can be read not only as a
far-seeing disquisition on justice but as a Hellenic guide for a
guardian elite in the manipulation of the people. Western
acolytes of Eastern thought often use such ambiguity to their advantage, exploiting metaphors of Eastern sages to render completely self-contradictory arguments intelligible, if not exactly
coherent. Ambiguity is no virtue in itself; rather, it demands
clarification and elucidation.
When many quasi-religious Asian tract s are viewed from a
*social* standpoint — which social ecology always requires — some of
their ambiguity seems to disappear. In traditional China, a fatalistic
peasantry was an easily manipulable peasantry, however “softly” it
dealt with nature — which was not quite as “soft” as the Western
imagination tends to picture it. In this respect, Leon E. Stover’s
*The Cultural Ecology of Chinese Civilization* is a much-needed companion
reader to Taoist and Buddhist literature.[50] The peasant village or
Green Circle (ch’ing chuan) of the north — a sobriquet that Stover
applies to Chinese villages generally — was traditionally the object
of systematic plunder by an elite. This elite fostered a privileged
“high culture” that patently justified their exploitation of the
peasantry in the name of a “Great Connected Whole.” What was
“great,” alas, was often what lay in the best interests of those who
considered themselves “great,” not necessarily of the peasantry,
who also formed part of the “whole.” Ecologically, the language of
“connectedness” in the Tao Te Ching is enchantingly “naturalistic.”
Socially, however, it provided a rhetorical patina for unchallenged
despotism in which peasant and elite were “connected” not by a
mutualistic symbiosis but by a parasitism in which the peasant was
the host and the gentleman the parasite.
Folk culture was separated from high culture by the
illiteracy and contraction of the peasant village to an introverted,
parochial, and self-enclosed universe — one that kept Chinese
society fragmented, hierarchical, and socially immobile. Villagers’
conceptions of nature were disconcerting: human life was seen in
the most passive and resigned perspective, as a steady demographic flow into the “Sink of Death.” Even divested of its institutional and ideological trappings, Taoism historically almost
certainly shaped the peasantry into a social body without choice,
motivation, respite from poverty, or hope of escaping being
drained into the “Sink.” In a “naturalistic” credo less of nurture
than of unrelenting destiny, piety was intermingled with acquiescence toward one’s fate, and toil was intermingled with
“sanctimonious husbandry,” as Stover calls it. From the viewpoint
of the elite, the peasants’ pride in their husbandry was less important than their vulnerability to exploitation.[51]
It is not my purpose to dwell at any great length on the
Asian heart that so often dazzles the Western head. What is
more important here is that this head is more mechanistic, instrumental, and inorganic than it cares to admit. Much that passes for ecological thinking today is as dim methodologically as it
is starry-eyed ideologically. Behind the “Third Wave” that is rolling over us, the “new paradigm” that is shifting us, the “feedback” that is electrifying us, and the “woodpaths” that are
guiding us, is a bizarre form of thinking that is as airy on its
spiritual peaks as it is crudely mechanistic at its hypothetico-deductive base. These contradictory “ecological zones,” as it
were, reflect serious ambiguities in nature philosophy itself:
namely, its potential to nourish reaction as well as revolution,
often with the same visions that fed a Blake at one extreme and
a Wagner at the other. These “ecological zones” must be briefly
surveyed if the project of thinking ecologically is to be seriously
explored.
*** Spiritual Mechanism
At the peril of standing very much at odds with what is voiced
these days in ecological philosophy, let me say that the problem of
dualism — the mode of thought that counterposes mind to body,
thought to reality, and society to nature — which receives so much
emphasis in ecological literature is giving way to the more serious
problem of reductionism.
Dualism and reductionism, in fact, are usually deeply entangled with each other. A crude dualism tends to foster its
counterpart in an equally crude monism that simplifies all of
reality into a single, often homogeneous agency, force, substance,
or energy source. Hegel caustically called this “a night in which
all cows are black.” The mystical sparks of light that appear in this
“night” should not deceive us. That reductionist notions glimmer
with words like Spirit, cosmic energy, vital forces, and
*energy centers* barely conceals the fact that reductionism emerges from
ways of thinking that are no less mechanistic, instrumental, and
analytical than the hypothetico-deductive mentality that has assumed such supremacy over the past two centuries of Western
thought Seemingly mystical, spiritual, and even organismic conclusions are often deduced by means of hypothetico-deductive
approaches, which in turn infect the entire project of “reenchanting” the world with dismally “disenchanting” instrumental underpinnings. Indeed, as we shall see, “method” can never be
blandly detached from the content it yields, just as the means one
uses in politics and life generally significantly determines the
ends one pursues.
One has only to consider the current love affair between
ecological philosophy and systems theory to observe this reductionism in its most popular, untutored, and syncretic form. Fritjof
Capra’s widely read *The Turning Point* can be taken as an example.
“The creative unfolding of life toward forms of ever increasing
complexity,” we learn, “remained an unsolved mystery for more
than a century after Darwin, but recent study has outlined the
contours of a theory of evolution that promises to shed light on
this striking characteristic of living organisms. This is a systems
theory that focuses on the dynamics of self-transcendence and is
based on the work of a number of scientists from various disciplines” — he mentions, among others, Ilya Prigogine, Gregory
Bateson, and Ervin Laszlo, to single out those who are widely
known in the United States. Capra continues:
The basic dynamics of evolution, according to the
new systems view, begins with a system of homeostasis — a state of dynamic balance characterized by
multiple independent fluctuations. When the system is disturbed it has the tendency to maintain its
stability by means of negative feedback mechanisms, which tend to reduce the deviation from the
balanced state. However, this is not the only possibility. Deviations may also be reinforced internally through positive feedback, either in response to
environmental changes or spontaneously without
any external influence. The stability of a living system is continually tested by its fluctuations, and at
certain moments one or several of them may become so strong that they drive the system over an
instability into an entirely new structure, which
will again be fluctuating and relatively stable. The
stability of living systems is never absolute. It will
persist as long as the fluctuations remain below a
critical size, but any system is always ready to transform itself, always ready to evolve. This basic model
for evolution, worked out for chemical dissipative
structures by Prigogine and his collaborators, has
since been applied successfully to describe the
evolution of various biological, social, and ecological systems.[52]
Almost everything that is troubling about spiritual mechanism,
from its terminology to its thought, is contained in this telling passage. Systems theory is certainly useful in explaining the operation of systems, especially ones so structured as to lend themselves
to systems theory analysis, just as the equations of physics can explain any phenomenon that can be reduced to the terms of
physics. What serious people in ecological philosophy have to ask
themselves is whether evolution, let alone self-transcendence, can
really be reduced to “dynamics,” “interdependent fluctuations,
“feedback mechanisms” — or even “inputs” and’outputs — that do
not differ in principle from the Newtonian orientation toward
phenomena or from La Mettrie’s eighteenth-century description
of human beings as machines. If there is anything developmental
or evolutionary (as distinguished from merely kinetic) about a systems theory “paradigm,” it is simply that some relatively homeo-static phenomena, conceived precisely as systems, may
replaced with other, hopefully complex systems. In either case,
despite the imagery that Capra tries to form in the reader’s mind,
we cannot properly speak of one mechanism being qualitativey
transformed into another. If the essential problem of organic
development is reduced at all its levels to “feedback loops” an
“fluctuations,” our thinking has not advanced beyond Cartesian
and Hobbesian mechanism, however lavishly we speak of the
“coevolution of an organism *plus* its environment,” of “wholeness,” or of Taoist sagacity and Franciscan theology.[53]
There is a physical basis to everything that physics
“Taoist,” Newtonian, or Prigoginian — describes with varying
degrees of exactness and at various levels of physical development But this fact is no more a warrant for casting *all* phenomena
in terms of these descriptions than reducing the entire world to
matter and motion. Indeed, such reductionism is fatal to any form
of organismic thinking. Capra’s explication a systems theory of
evolution describes thought as “free.”[54] But to speak of “autonomy
and freedom of choice” in nature, pure and simple, is to diminish
the ethical meaning of the words. Nature may be an evolving
*ground* for autonomy, freedom, and an increasing measure of
choice, but a ground *is no more identical with the ethics it sustains*
than nutrients in soil are identical with the plants they sustain.
Autonomy and freedom presuppose human intellection, the
power to conceptualize and generalize. Their domain must be explicated in cultural, logical, and, within very definite limits,
biological terms — not in terms of a cosmic “dynamics” that is
“basically open and indeterminate.”[55] Indeed, to flippantly confuse indeterminacy with autonomy and openness with freedom is
to shift from one level to another as carelessly as one stirs a cup of
tea. Capra’s approach to “freedom” renders indeterminacy and
statistical probability in physics coequal with human social
freedom, without the least regard for the staggering complexity
of social institutions, wayward individual proclivities, diverse
cultural traditions, and conflicting personal wills.
Ilya Prigogine has attempted to explain the organic
process of evolution through “chemical dissipative structures,” in
wduch various systems are formed in succession, each hopefully
oif greater complexity than the ones that preceded it.[56] In a succession of systems, these “dissipative structures,” which can be
mia thematic ally formulated, are shown to succeed each other: a
system approaches a “far from equilibrium” situation, which
miarks its transition to a new system. Here, as “dissipative structures” replace the phases of growth, development gives way to
thermodynamics. Nor does a system of positive feedback, upon
wdiich Prigoginian systems theory depends, *allow for a concept of potentiality: it is rather chance and stochastic phenomena* that act as
“mediating” phases between one “dissipative structure” and
another. Confronted with “far from equilibrium” disorder and
succeeding orderly systems, speculative thought is reduced to
mere observation. Indeed, a system approaching transition may
not assume an immanently predictable form thereafter — it may
simply fall apart into “chaos.” These systems have, in effect, no
internal developmental logic.
Prigogine’s mathematics can no more explain the biological,
social, and personal differentiae that make up reality, even
with the aid of winged Taoist metaphors, than a heap of bricks
can form itself into a Gothic cathedral through the “fluctuations”
involved in positive feedback. One could, with equal aplomb, try
to reduce organic metabolism to Einstein’s cosmic formula
E=mc2, simply because it is cosmic. At the risk of adding to
philosophy’s already heavy burden of “fallacies,” I would define
the “reductionist fallacy” as the application of the most general
formulas to the most detailed particulars, in the belief that what is
universal and seemingly all-encompassing must necessarily explain what is highly particular and uniquely individual.[57] At best,
a formula, a “paradigm,” or more properly, a philosophy, may
provide the basis for an orientation toward reality at a clearly
definable level of reality. Ironically, the more universal, abstract,
and mathematical a formula is, the more likely that its very
generality will limit it when it is applied to concrete, highly particularized phenomena, E=mc2 is *too* cosmic to explain such richly articulated or mediated modes of reality as natural evolution,
organic metabolism, social development, and personal behavior.
Not surprisingly. New Age acolytes of ecology become
authentic reductionists. “God,” “Energy,” “Being,” “Love,” “Interconnectedness,” and a whole repertoire of metaphors are invoked
that serve to homogenize the particular and divest it of its richness and diversity. When this approach proves too abstract, it is
always possible to create a pastiche of ill-digested “paradigms”
and theories, regardless of the fact that their premises and logic
may conflict with each other. Here eclecticism, which usually
clouds radically different ways of thinking and the myth that we
all share a “common goal,” becomes the last redoubt for sheer intellectual sloppiness.
The language that the more sophisticated systems theorists
use reflects the concepts they bring to their “paradigms.” Complex results are stripped down to their most elemental levels so
that they can be handled in physico-mathematical terms. That
hypothetico-deductive analyses have immense value in relations
that are authentically dynamic or mechanical is not in question
here; their value in these domains of knowledge cannot be surpassed. What is troubling is that systems theory tends to become
a highly imperialistic ideological approach that stakes out a claim
to the totality of development, indeed to reason out and explain
virtually all phenomena. *If* natural evolution, organic metabolism, and personal behavior were systems, *then* systems theory in
all its self-fulfilling grandeur would seem to work admirably.
That this “if-then” conversion (and I will have more to say about
these later) denudes phenomena of many complex qualities that
do not lend themselves to systems analysis is conveniently lost in
a shuffle of grandiose metaphors that appeal more to an ever-yielding heart than to a demanding logical mind.
By contrast, the power of the West’s organismic — more
precisely, dialectical — tradition (even at Hegel’s highly conceptual level) lies in *building up* the differentiae of natural and social
phenomena from what is implicit in their abstract level — not in
corrosively *reducing* their richly articulated concreteness to
abstract, logically manipulable “data” The difference between
the two approaches could not be stated sharply enough. Dialectic, as we shall see, tries to elicit the development of phenomena
from their level of abstract “homogeneity,” latent with the rich
differentiation that will mark their maturity, while systems theory
tries to reduce phenomena from their highly articulated particularity to the level of homogeneous abstraction so necessary
for mathematical symbolization. Dialectic, in effect, is a logic of
evolution *from abstraction toward differentiation*; systems theory is a
logic of devolution *from differentiation toward abstraction*.
For the present, it is important to note that the careless use
of the word *complexity* often tells us nothing whatever about the
nature of a complex phenomenon and its development, anymore
than the careless use of the word process tells us anything about
the nature of a complex *process*. Many complex phenomena,
viewed in an ethical or even in a survival sense, are positively
harmful and woefully unecological, such as the complex,
presumably self-regulating market — whose advocates are, in fact,
captivated by the theoretical premises of Prigogine’s version of
systems theory. Nor can we ignore complex processes that can
degrade a biologically desirable development, such as epidemics
that exterminate ecologically valuable species.
Development without a “goal in it, or purpose,” as Capra
declares somewhat dolefully, can be equally meaningless, despite
the fact that his “systems theory of life” finds a “recognizable pattern of development.”[58] The word *pattern* — or for that matter,
*paradigm* — is no substitute for the idea of *tendency* in speculative
philosophy. In the absence of everything but a system of positive
feedback that may or may not yield complexity, Capra, like many
of his associates, is obliged to turn to the East and import an
ethics to render systems theory meaningful—even in flat contravention of his Western methodology. In a sudden leap, the language (not to speak of the conceptual framework) of
*The Turning Point* undergoes a startling transformation. Invocations of “a new
holistic worldview,” “a conceptual shift from structure to
rhythm” — extended to the “rise and fall” of civilizations, indeed
to the “planet as a whole ... as it spins around its axis and moves
around the sun” — suddenly overlie the “dynamics” and “feedback, loops” that actually form the eminently Western methodological underpinnings of his “systems view of life.” “Eastern
mystical traditions, especially in Taoism,” are thrown into a potpourri of formulations whose only similarity is metaphoric.[59]
“The idea of fluctuations as the basis of order is one of the basic
themes in Taoist texts,” Capra apprises us, making it seem in the
most superficial way that Taoism parallels Prigogine’s systems
approach. But “fluctuations,” like “cycles,” have been used from,
time immemorial to explain stagnation rather than evolution,
fixity rather than change, and eternality rather than development. Syncretically placing fluctuations in systems theory on a
par with fluctuations in Taoism is about as sound as placing the
electromagnetic “attraction” in physics on par with Eros as a “cosmic” source of affinity and unity. From a methodological viewpoint, Prigogine’s mathematical formulation of chemical dissipative structures fits just as snugly into Newton’s mechanistic
sensibility as the corpuscular theory of light fits into the wave
theory. These conceptual frameworks meld together because they
derive from the same hypothetico-deductive, indeed clearly
mechanistic mentality.
Nor is it helpful to recast the “systems view of life” into
Gregory Bateson’s theoretical framework. Here, materiality is dissolved into interrelationships and then subjectivized as “minds”
This framework might be somewhat comprehensible to an Eastern sage, but it divests substance, indeed nature itself, of its very
physicality. Abandoning the study of things — living or not — for a
study of the relationships between them is as one-sided and
reductionist as abandoning the study of relationships for the
things they interrelate. If traditional materialist mechanism
strongly emphasized the object, often with results that inhibited
speculation beyond the given state of affairs, Bateson’s emphasis
on relationships verges on a subjectivism that could almost be
taken for solipsism if one did not know more about Bateson’s
work as a whole. The claim that “all experience is subjective” and
that “our brains make the images that we think we ‘perceive’”
borders on an idealist counterpart of Jacob Moleschott’s equally
crude materialist maxim, “No thought without phosphorus.”[60]
Thinking once presupposed a knowledge of thought as it
unfolded over millennia of philosophical and social development.
Today, the intellectual span of the present generation barely extends beyond a decade and is marked by a disquieting bias in
favor of journalistic glibness. That ecological acolytes of systems
theory often merely stand Newtonian mechanism on its head yet
receive no criticism from ecologically oriented intellectuals is
evidence of the cultural Dark Ages that are gathering around us.
We are even witnessing a revival of Hume’s “is-ought” criticism,
which denies speculative thought the right to reason from the
“what-is” to the “what-should-be.” This positivistic mousetrap is a
problem not in logic but in ethics — notably, the right of the ethical “should-be” to enjoy an objective status. The problem of constituting an objective ethics, which confounded the Frankfurt
School, is no less serious than Hume’s quarrel with organized
religion. Speculative philosophy by definition claims that reason
can project *beyond* the given state of affairs, whether to Plato’s exemplary domain of forms or Marx and Kropotkin’s visions of a
cooperative society. To remain within the “what-is” in the name of
logical consistency is to deny reason the right to assert goals,
values, and social relationships that provide a voice to the claims
of ecology as a social discipline.
These theoretical problems have an eminently practical significance. In all cases they reveal an intellectual glibness that dissolves that which is concrete in the ecological picture, indeed the
life-forms that give substantially to the various systems, into interrelationships, “dynamics,” and “minds” that Capra, Prigogine,
Bateson, et al., abstract into lifeless categories. Thus reductionism
not only turns complex organisms and their equally complex
evolution into mechanical “fluctuations,” debasing concrete organisms into abstract interrelationships; it turns life in all its rich
specificity into an abstraction, thereby divesting nature of the
variety, indeed the species-individuality so essential to an understanding of nature’s fecundity and its evolutionary impetus.[61]
*** Humanism and Antihumanism
“Humanity,” currently so unfulfilled and divided against itself,
has scarcely realized its potentialities. But in much current
“ecological” thinking the concept of humanity is no less sucked
into the ideological black hole.[62] Ideologically, the phenomenon
of human self-hatred (and human beings seem to be the one
species that has the ability to luxuriate in self-hatred) takes a
number of forms: a logically ambiguous “biocentrism” and often
strident antihumanism are set against “anthropocentrism” and
humanism — presumably the cardinal sins of an abstract “Man”
who is determined to despoil an equally abstract “Nature.” If
systems theory divests nonhuman life of its specificity, biocentrism and antihumanism divest human life of social
development. Society becomes an abstraction that somehow is
inflicted upon “Nature” without any regard for such social
characteristics as hierarchy, domination, and the state. As a
result, a simplistic biologism emerges, often structured around
“natural laws,” that sees “Man” and humanism as a curse that
afflicts “Nature” with ecological degradation. As a result, some
voices in the ecology movement call for a moral “biospheric
democracy” in which humanity’s “right” to live and fulfill itself
is equatable with that same “right” in butterflies, ants, whales,
apes, and — yes — pathogenic viruses and germs.
Viewed heuristically, biocentrism is an effort to bridle
“human” arrogance toward other life-forms and defy the present
destruction of the biosphere. But how long one can continue to
belabor “humanity” for its affronts to the biosphere without distinguishing between rich and poor, men and women, whites and
people of color, exploiters and exploited, is a nagging problem
that many ecological philosophers have yet to resolve, or perhaps
even recognize. Biocentrism, for all the caveats its supporters
issue to qualify it, strikes me as bluntly misanthropic and less an
ecological principle than an argument against the human species
itself as a life-form.
Taken separately, perhaps, the intentions of their adherents may be good, even as these theories are seriously faulty.
United into a single ensemble, however, they develop a harsh
logic and create an arena for explicitly vicious views. It was not
surprising that David Foreman, then of Earth First! and an
avowed acolyte of “deep ecology,” could advance the following
“ecological” verdict on the Third World:
When I tell people how the worst thing we could do
in Ethiopia is to give aid — the best thing would be
to just let nature seek its own balance, to let the
people there just starve ... they think that is
monstrous. But the alternative is that you go in and
save these half-dead children who never will live a
whole life. Their development will be stunted. And
what’s going to happen in ten years’ time is that
twice as many people will suffer and die.
Likewise, letting the USA be an overflow
valve for problems in Latin America is not solving a
thing. It’s just putting more pressure on resources
we have in the USA. It is just causing more destruction of our wilderness, more poisoning of water and
air, and it isn’t helping the problems in Latin
America.[63]
Regrettably, it is all too easy to interpret such remarks as
an apologia for imperialism, racism, and genocide. To consider
starvation as merely an “alternative” to the civil war that wracked
Ethiopia and the destruction of so much of the cultural integrity
of Latin American villages by (largely American) corporate interests reveals a shocking social amnesia. It is breathtaking to contemplate the extent to which this “ecological” ensemble of ideas
deflects public attention from the *social origins* of ecological
problems. That anything besides “nature” is seeking its “balance”
in the Third World seems to elude Foreman, whose obfuscation of
social problems expresses the logic of a reductionist “ecology.”
Such “reverence for the earth” stifles even the modest decencies
of middle-class virtues like empathy and concern for the plight of
hungry children. “Earth wisdom” of this kind could well leave us
with a “love” of the planet but no care for the underprivileged
who make up so much of the human species.
Yet Foreman’s remarks are not idiosyncratic. Quite to the
contrary: am authoritarian streak is latent in a crude biologism
that conceals an ever-diminishing humaneness with “natural
law” and papers over the fact that it is *capitalism* that is at work
here, not an abstract “Humanity” and “Society.” This authoritarian mentality sometimes coexists with pious appeals to
variants of Eastern spirituality, placing a saintly mask on the
ruthless egoism that stems from bourgeois greed. “Ecological
thinking” of this kind is all the more sinister because it subverts
the organic, indeed dialectical thinking that can rescue us from
reductionism. An unbridgeable gulf separates social ecology from
the neo-Malthusianism that the ensemble of biocentrism, antihumanism, and “natural law” theory have spawned. We are grimly in need of a “reenchantment” of humanity — to use the
quasi-mystical jargon of our day — with a fluid, organismic, and
dialectical rationality. For it is in this *human* rationality that nature
ultimately actualizes its own evolution of subjectivity over long
aeons of neural and sensory development. There is nothing more
natural than humanity’s capacity to conceptualize, generalize, relate
ideas, engage in symbolic communication, and innovate changes in the
world around it, not merely to adapt to the conditions it finds at hand.
For biocentric, antihumanist, and “natural law” advocates to set
their faces against the self-realization of nature in an ecologically
oriented humanity and dialectical thought is to foster the image
of a blighted humanity. No less than Adam and Eve’s acquisition
of knowledge, humanity’s power of thought becomes its abiding
“original sin.”
*** Ecologizing the Dialectic
It is eminently *natural* for humanity to create a “second nature”
from its evolution in “first nature.” By *second nature*, I mean the
development of uniquely human culture, with a wide variety
of institutionalized human communities, effective human technics, richly symbolic languages, and carefully managed sources
of nutriment. Dualism, in all its forms, has opposed these two
natures to each other, as antagonists. Monism, in turn, often
dissolves one into the other — be it liberalism, fascism, or more
recently, the biocentrism that so closely approximates
misanthropic antihumanism. These monist ideologies differ
primarily in whether they want to dissolve first nature into
second or second nature into first.
What these dualisms and monisms have in common is an
acceptance of domination. Classically, the counterpart of the
domination of nature by man” has been the “domination of man
by nature. Just as Marxism and liberalism see the former as a
desideratum that emerges out of the latter, so enthusiasts of
‘natural law” accept the latter as a fact and condemn efforts to
achieve the former. These views are deeply flawed — not only because they are conceptually one-sided or simply wrong, but because of the way they are philosophically structured and worked
out. The real question, I submit, is not whether second nature
parallels, opposes, or blandly “participates” in an “egalitarian”
first nature;[64] rather, it is how second nature is *derived* from first
nature. More specifically, in what ways did the highly graded and
many-phased evolution from first nature into second give rise to
social institutions, forms of interactions between people, and an
interaction between first and second nature that, in the best of
cases, enriches both and yields a second nature that has an evolutionary development of its own? The ecological crisis we face
today is very much a crisis in the emergence of society out of biology, in the problems (the rise of hierarchy, domination, patriarchy, classes, and the state) that unfolded with this development,
and in the liberatory pathways that provide an alternative to this
warped history.
The fact that first and second nature exist and can never be
dualized into “parallels” or simplistic ally reduced to each other
accounts, in great part, for my phrase *social ecology*. Additionally,
social ecology has the special meaning that the ecological crisis
that beleaguers us stems from a social crisis, a crisis that the crude
biologism of “deep ecology” generally ignores. Still further, that
the resolution of this social crisis can only be achieved by reorganizing society along rational lines, imbued with an ecological
philosophy and sensibility.
Such a philosophy and sensibility cannot be eclectically
patched together from bits and pieces of mechanism and mysticism, or of conventional reason and Eastern spirituality. One
could respect a consistently Eastern mystical view or a consistently Western mechanistic view, however one-sided or erroneous
each may be. But neither view can fruitfully derive second nature
from first nature organically. That requires a mode of thought
that distinguishes the phases of the evolutionary continuum from
which second nature emerges and yet preserves first nature as
part of the process. Common sense betrays us with its demand for
conceptual fixity; mysticism, in turn, deflects us from rationality
that goes substantially beyond poetic metaphors. A good deal of
ecological thinking today, as we have seen, partakes of both
modes — the mechanistic and the mystical — in an opportunistic,
“catch-as-catch-can” manner, rather than restructuring its mode
of thought in an authentically organic manner.
This much should be clear: the purely deductive logic that
we use to build bridges, budget our income and expenses, plan
our everyday lives, and calculate our chances of “making out” in
the world holds no promise of grasping the richly articulated or
mediated development that both unites and differentiates first
and second nature. Common sense demands only inference, consistency, and the verification that ordinary sensory experience
provides. Apart from the inductively apprehended particulars
that help us arrive (often quite intuitively) at the concrete
premises for our inferences, we normally tend to deduce our
ideas schematically, as a series of well-ordered and rigidly fixed
concepts. Truth in this everyday logical domain is normally little
more than consistency. Thus, we are held to be “logical” when
our conclusions can be framed into fixed categories — supported,
to be sure, by those atomized isolates known as “brute facts.” This
achievement is celebrated as “clarity” and its results as “certainty.” To conceive of any form of reasoning other than a
hypothetico-deductive logic is evidence of fuzzy-headedness.
Facts, you know, are facts, and truth is truth. Consistency, the formalistic “if-then” propositions that make up conventional logic,
together with experience as a sequence of “clear-cut” data and the
eminently practical results that conventional logic achieves — all,
taken together, are the means to “think clearly” and understand
the “real world.”
Yet there is a highly personal sphere of life in which we
think very differently from conventional reason. We do not deal
with children the way we deal with our business affairs and the
pragmatics of everyday living. We see children as *developing*
beings who pass through necessary phases of growth and increasing capabilities. We try not to impose more demands upon
them than they can adequately handle at their age (assuming, to
be sure, that we are rational and humane people). Nor do we try
to afflict them with problems they cannot yet resolve. We sense a
flow in their lives that involves the actualization of their potentialities at different levels of their development. It requires no unusual perception to recognize the infant that lingers on in the
child, the child that lingers on in the youth, the youth that lingers
on in the adult — in short, the *cumulative* nature of human
development, in contrast to mere substitution and succession
Only a fool believes that the man or woman could — or should —
completely replace the boy or girl. Properly understood, a mature
person is not an inventory of test results and measurements. He
or she is an individual *biography*, the developmental embodiment
of partially or wholly realized qualities that an environment surely conditions but whose inherent makeup would ultimately
determine his or her development *if* society acquired a highly rational form.
However intuitive it may be, this kind of thinking is structured around not deduction but *eduction*. If deduction consists of
the inferential “if-then” steps we take, with due reverence for
consistency, to arrive at unshakable and clearly defined judgments about “brute facts,” eduction fully manifests and articulates the latent possibilities of phenomena. Eduction is a phased
process in which “if” is not a fixed hypothetical premise but
rather a *potentiality*. “Steps” in eduction are not mere inferences
but stages of *development*. “Consistency,” far from being an imposed canon of logic based on principles of identity, contradiction, and the excluded middle, is the immanent process we
properly call *self-development*. Finally, “then” is the full *actualization* of potentiality in its rich, self-incorporative “stages” of
growth, differentiation, maturation, and wholeness. That the
“mature” and “whole” are never so complete that they cease to be
the potentiality for a still further development represents an
ecological change I am advancing here.
Which brings us to the problem of what we are obliged to
modify in the dialectical philosophy of its two most outstanding
voices, Aristotle and Hegel, in order to render it an *ecological* mode
of thought.[65] ‘To do this,’ we must briefly summarize what an
ecological dialectic shares with the Aristotelian and Hegelian.
Dialectical philosophy moves from the undifferentiated abstract
to the highly differentiated concrete (while most commonsensical
forms of thought move in the opposite direction). In this respect
dialectic picks up the thread of classical eduction and goes
beyond it, moving from that which is implicit in bare potentiality
to its realization in a fully articulated actuality. Much of Greek
philosophy expressed this problematic as that of the emergence
of the Many from the One: in Aristotle’s work, the apogee of classical thought, “a conception of substance, or the real, as the goal
toward which develops a potential being that, save as ultimately
realized, is neither real nor intelligible, dominates the whole
course of Aristotle’s speculation,” observes G.R.G. Mure in a very
pithy formulation. “Follow him as he applies it in every sphere
which he investigates; watch it grow from this initial abstract formula into a concrete universe of thought; and you may hope to
grasp the essential meaning of his philosophy”[66] The same could
be said of Hegel, whose elaboration of this Aristotelian motif is
more subjectivized and informed, although at times it is cluttered
by the mountain of problematics that had been added to Western
philosophy since Aristotle’s time.
An ecological dialectic would have to address the fact
that Aristotle and Hegel did not work with an evolutionary
theory of nature but rather saw the natural world more as a
*scala naturae*, a ladder of “Being,” than as a flowing continuum
An ecological dialectic introduces evolution into this tradition
and replaces the notion of a *scala naturae* with a richly mediated
continuum. Both thinkers were more profoundly influenced by
Plato than their writings would seem to indicate, with the result
that in the case of Hegel, we move within a realm of concept
more than history (however historical Hegel’s dialectic invariably was). Hegel was strongly preoccupied with the “idea” of nature rather than with its existential details, although he honored
this preoccupation in the breach. Finally, the overarching” teleology of the two philosophers tends to subordinate the contingency, spontaneity, and creativity that mark natural phenomena.[67]
Hegel, with his strong theological bent, terminated the unfolding of the world in an “Absolute” that encompasses it in an identity of subject and object. In an ecological dialectic, by contrast
there would be no terminality that could culminate in a God or
an Absolute. “Actuality,” to use Hegel’s special term, is the almost momentary culmination of maturity, so that the objectivity
of the potential, which is crucial for an objective ethics, is subordinated to its actualization.
English translations of Hegel often erroneously render *real*
and *actual* as synonyms in certain passages, allowing the
Hegelian “real” to be conceived as the actualization of the potential
— a failing that I believe should be corrected. What is less “real”
than Hegel’s “reality” — notably the “brute facts” or the given “is”
of common sense — would more closely correspond to what
Hegel considers “the apparent” (*das Erscheinende*). From an
ecological viewpoint, this mistranslation could lead to much confusion. Hence, I have used the word *real* to mean simply “what-is,” not “what is necessarily latent in the potential.” The *actual*
remains very much what Hegel meant it to mean: the rational
realization of the potential, as distinguished from the “real” as
the existential.[68] Finally, an ecological dialectic greatly modifies
the creative role that Hegel imparted to strife, often interpreted
as mere “antithesis” (which is roughly as far as Theodor Adorno
takes the dialectic in his *Negative Dialectics*), but not without ignoring the presence of strife in human history. It emphasizes that
the dialectic, no less in Hegel’s than in my own thinking, undergoes differentiation through a transcendence beyond mere antithesis, notably what Hegel called an *Aufhebung* or negation of
the negation. Dialectic is thus a philosophy of progress in which
there is a growing elaboration and self-consciousness, insofar as
the world is rational.
Dialectic, let me emphasize, is not merely “change,” “motion, or even process, all banal imputations to the contrary
notwithstanding. Nor can it be subsumed under “process
philosophy.” Dialectic is *development*, not only change; it is *derivation*, not only motion; it is *mediation*, not only process; and it is
*cumulative*, not only continuous. That it is also change, motion,
process, and a continuum tells us only part of its true content.
But denied its immanent self-directiveness and its entelechial
eduction of the potential into the actual, this “process
philosophy, indeed this remarkable notion of *causality*, ceases to
be dialectic. Instead, it becomes a mere husk that our current
flock of “eco”-faddists can reduce to “kinetics,” “dynamics,
“fluctuations,” and “feedback loops” — the same mechanistic verbiage with which systems theory dresses itself up as a developmental philosophy.
As Hegel warned in the course of educing the complexity
of the dialectical process: knowledge has “no other object than to
draw out what is inward or implicit and thus to become objective.” But if
that which is implicit comes into existence, it certainly passes into change, yet it *remains one and the same*.... The plant, for example, does not lose itself
in mere indefinite change. From the germ much is
produced when at first nothing was to be seen; but
the whole of what is brought forth, if not
developed, is yet hidden and ideally contained
within itself. The principle of this *projection into existence* is that the germ cannot remain merely implicit, but is impelled toward development, since it
presents the contradiction of being only implicitly
and yet not desiring to be so.[69]
Thus dialectic is not *wayward* motion, the mere kinetics of
change. There is a rational “end in view” — not one that is preordained, to state this point from an ecological viewpoint rather
than a theological one, but that actualizes what is implicit in the
potential. Every “if-then” proposition is premised not on any if
that springs into one’s head like a gambler s hunch; it posits a
potentiality that has its ancestry in the dialectical processes that
preceded it.
Reductionism breaks this process down to the most undifferentiated interactions it can formulate. But it does so at the cost
of demolishing the various phases or “moments” (to use Hegelian
terminology) from which the process is literally constituted. A
human being is clearly an ensemble of chemicals. While reductionism can explain its existence as a physico-chemical phenomenon, it cannot comprehend it as a remarkably complex form of
life. Chemical analysis provides us with no substitute for the multitude of forms, relationships, processes, and environments that
the organic creates for itself as it metabolically sustains its own
“selfhood” in distinction from other “selves.” Indeed, carried too
far into a lower level of phenomena, reduction leads to dissolution, so that the very integrity of a given level of phenomena — be
it social, biological, chemical, or physical — simply disappears into
mere “matter” and “motion.” In a kind of ideological entropy,
thought no longer has the differentiae with which to define its
subject matter, let alone explore it. As the complex is trimmed
down to its “irreducible” components, the whole that forms the
very premises of thought disappears into a meaningless, indeed
formless heap of “matter,” thereby erasing the very boundaries
that give *definition* to a phenomenon as a component of a more
complex “whole.”
In the organic world, the metabolic activity of the simplest
life-forms constitutes the sense of self-identity, however germinal,
from which nature acquires a rudimentary subjectivity. Not only
does this rudimentary subjectivity (which reductionism necessarily cannot encompass) derive from the metabolic process of
self-maintenance, a process that defines any life-form as a unique
whole; it extends itself beyond self-maintenance to become a
striving activity, not unlike the development from the vegetative
to the animative, that ultimately yields mind, will, and the potentiality for freedom. Conceived dialectically, organic evolution is,
in a broad sense, subjective insofar as life-forms begin to exercise
choices in adapting to new environments — a conception that
stands much at odds with that clearly definable fixity we blissfully call “clear thinking.” Systems theory enters into the reductionist tableau in a sinister way: by dissolving the subjective
element in biological phenomena so that they can be treated as
mathematical symbols, systems theory permits evolutionary interaction, subjective development, and even process itself, to be
taken over by “the system,” just as the individual, the family, and
the community are destructured into “the System” embodied by
the economic corporation and the state. Life ceases to have subjectivity and becomes a mechanism in which the tendency of lifeforms toward ever-greater elaboration is replaced with “feedback
loops,” and their evolutionary antecedents with programmed “information.” A “systems view of life” literally conceives of life as a
system, not only as “fluctuations” and “cycles” — mechanistic as
these concepts are in themselves.
Despite the external selective factors with which Darwinians describe evolution, the tendency of life toward a greater
complexity of selfhood — a tendency that yields increasing
degrees of subjectivity — constitutes the internal or immanent impulse of evolution toward growing self-awareness. This evolutionary dialectic constitutes the essence of life as a self-maintaining organism that bears the *potential* for the development of self-conscious organisms. Dialectic, in effect, is not merely a “logic” or a “method” that can be bounced around and
“applied” promiscuously to a content. It has no “handbook” other
than *reason itself* to guide those who seek to develop a dialectical
sensibility. Dialectic can no more be applied to problems in engineering than Einstein’s general theory of relativity can be applied to plumbing; these problems can best be resolved by
conventional forms of logic, common sense, and the pragmatic
knowledge acquired through experience. Dialectic can only explicate a rationally developmental phenomenon, just as systems
theory can only explicate the workings of a fluctuating and cyclical system. The kind of verification that validates or invalidates
the soundness of dialectical reasoning, in turn, must be *developmental*, not relatively static or for that matter “fluctuating” kinds of phenomena.
Hence, it distorts the very meaning of dialectic to speak of
it as a “method.” Indeed, dialectical philosophy, properly conceived and freed of mechanistic presumptions, is an ongoing
protest against the myth of methodology: notably, that the “techniques” for thinking out a process can be separated from the
process itself. Its sensitivity for concrete phenomena, even when
they are distilled into “concepts,” as Hegel did, is what renders
dialectic such an existentially vital and palpably organismic
philosophy. It was Hegel’s genius to reintroduce Plato’s supra-mundane world of forms — an *exemplary* and hence a *moral* world,
not merely a metaphysical one — into reality and to develop
Aristotle’s notion of entelechy into a concept of “transcendence”
(*Anfhebung*) that nuances processes as mediated “moments in the
self-fulfillment of their potentialities.” Freed of its theological
trappings, dialectic *explains*, with a power beyond that of any
conventional logic, how the organic flow of first into second nature is a reworking of biological into social reality. Each phase or
“moment” pressed by its own internal logic into an antithetical
and ultimately a more transcendent form, emerges as a more complex unity-in-diversity that encompasses its earlier moments even
as it goes beyond them. Despite the imagery of strife that permeates the Hegelian version of this process, the ultimate point of
the Hegelian *Aufhebung* is reconciliation, not the nihilism of pure
negation. Moreover, norms — the actualization of the potential
“is” into the ethical “ought” — are anchored in the objective reality
of potentiality itself, not as it always “is,” to be sure, but as
“should be,” such that speculation becomes a valid account of
reality in its truth. Hegel, I would argue, radically expanded the
very concept of Being in philosophy and in the real world to encompass
the potential and its actualization into the rational “what-should-be”
not only as an existential “what-is.”[70]
Dialectical speculation, despite Hegel’s own view of the
retrospective function of philosophy, thus is *projective* in a sharply
critical sense (quite unlike “futurology,” which dissolves the future:
by making it a mere extrapolation of the present). In its restless
critique of reality we can call dialectic a “negative philosophy” — in
contrast, I should add, to Adorno’s nihilism or “negative dialectics.
By the same token, speculation is creative in that it ceaselessly contrasts the free, rational, and moral actuality of “what-could-be,
which inheres in nature’s thrust toward self-reflexivity, with the
existential reality of “what-is.”[71] Speculation can ask “why” (not
only “how”) the real has become the irrational — indeed, the inhuman and anti-ecological — precisely because dialectic alone is
capable of grounding an ecological ethics in the potential, that is,
in its objective possibilities for the realization of reason and truth.
This objectivization of possibilities — of potentiality continuous with its yet unrealized actualization — is the ground for a genuinely objective ethics, as distinguished from an ethical
relativism subject to the waywardness of the opinion poll. An
ecological dialectic, in effect, opens the way to an ethics that is
rooted in the objectivity of the potential, not in the commandments of a deity or in the eternality of a supramundane and transcendental “reality.” Hence, the “what-should-be” is not only
objective, it forms the objective critique of the given reality.
Human intervention into nature is inherent and inevitable. To argue that this intervention should not occur is utterly obfuscatory, since humanity’s second nature is not simply an
external imposition on biology’s first nature but is the result of
first nature’s inherent evolutionary process. What is at issue in
humanity’s transformation of nature is whether its practice is
consistent with an objective ecological ethics that is rationally
developed, not haphazardly divined, felt, or intuited. Minimally,
such an ecological ethics would involve human stewardship of
the planet. A humanity that failed to see that it is potentially nature rendered self-conscious and self-reflexive would separate itself from nature morally as well as intellectually. Second nature in
such a situation would literally be divested of its last ties to first
nature; worse, the vacuum left by the departure of consciousness
would be filled by blind market-oriented interests and an egoistic
marketplace mentality. In any case, there is no road back from
second to first nature, any more than second nature as it is now
constituted can rescue the biosphere from destruction with “technological fixes” and political reforms.
Given the massive ecological crisis that confronts us, intellectual confusion in the ecology movement may yield harmful
results of immeasurable proportions. In the present period of history, to carelessly heap fragments of ideas upon each other and
call this ecophilosophy is no longer an affordable luxury.
Stewardship of the earth need not consist of such accommodating
measures as the establishment of ecological wilderness zones or
half measures to patch up environmental dislocations. What it can
and should mean is a radical integration of second nature
first nature along far-reaching ecological lines, an integration that
would yield new ecocommunities, ecotechnologies, and an abiding
ecological sensibility that embodies nature’s thrust toward
self-reflexivity. For biocentrists and antihumanists to throw
word *arrogance* around whenever anyone cites human beings as
ethical and mental referents for nature and natural evolution is
manipulative. Nature without an active human presence would
be as unnatural as a tropical rainforest that lacked monkeys and
ants. Dialectic, it should be noted, is no less a critique of one
sidedness and simplicity than of existing reality and an adaptive
mentality to the status quo. Cast in radical ecological terms, it calls
for a denial of *centricity* as such, be it “anthropocentricity,”
“biocentricity,” or so-called “ecocentricity,” which is meant to include rocks and rivers as well as life-forms. A philosophy of organic development is above all a philosophy of *wholeness* in which
evolution reaches a degree of unity-in-diversity such that nature
can *act* upon itself rationally through rational human agency, with
its derivation in nature’s potential for freedom and conceptual
thought.
In the intermediate zone between first and second nature
that saw the graded passage of biological evolution into social, social evolution began to assume increasingly hierarchical form;
Whether this could have been avoided is impossible to say — and
meaningless to divine. In any case, social evolution unfolded in the
direction of hierarchical, class-oriented, and statist institution
giving rise to the nation-state and ultimately, albeit not inevitably,
to a capitalist economy. In our own time, the massive penetration
of this economy into society as a whole has produced an even more
serious distortion of second nature. The market *economy*, which all
cultures from antiquity to recent times have resisted to one degree
or another, has essentially become a market *society*. This society is
historically unique. It identifies progress with competition rather
than cooperation. It views society as a realm for possessing things
rather than for elaborating human relationships. It creates a
morality based on growth rather than limit and balance. For the
first time in human history, society and community have been
reduced to little more than a huge shopping mall.
Unless ecology explores this warped development systematically — that is, unless it unearths its internal logic in a
reasoned and organismic way — its critical thrust will be entirely
lost and its integrity hopelessly impugned. Today, eclecticism and
reductionism — a hodgepodge of disconnected, even contradictory ideas degraded to their lowest common denominator — are
the most serious obstacles to the realization of this critical project.
Eclecticism may appeal to lazy minds that prefer slogans to
reasoned studies of society and its impact on the natural world.
But with lazy minds come lazy thoughts and a passive-receptive
mentality that increasingly renders the mind vulnerable to
authoritarian control.
*** Beyond First and Second Nature
We must try to bring the threads of our discussion together and
examine the important implications dialectic has for ecological
thinking. A “dialectical view of life” is a special form of process
philosophy. Its emphasis is not on change alone but on development. It is eductive rather than merely deductive, mediated rather
than merely processual, and cumulative rather than merely continuous. Its objectivity begins with the existence of the potential,
not with the mere facticity of the real; hence its ethics seeks the
“what-should-be” as a realm of *objective* possibilities. That “possibilities” are objective, albeit not in the sense of a simplistic
materialism, is dialectically justified by the perception that potentiality and its latent possibilities form an existential continuum
that constitutes the authentic world of truth — the world of the
“what-should-be,” not simply the world of the “what-is,” with all
its incompleteness and falsehood.
From a dialectical viewpoint, a change in a given level of
biotic, communal, or for that matter, social organization consists
not simply of the appearance of a new, possibly more complex ensemble of “feedback loops.” Rather, it consists of qualitatively
new attributes, interrelationships, and degrees of subjectivity
that express and radically condition the emergence of a new
potentiality, opening up a new realm of possibility with its own
unique tendency — not a greater or lesser number of “fluctuations” and “rhythms.” Moreover, this new potentiality is itself the
result of other actualizations of potentialities that, taken together
historically and cumulatively, constitute a developmental continuum — not a bullet “shot from a pistol” that explodes into Being
without a history of its own or a continuum of which it is part.[72]
Dialectical logic is an immanent logic of process — an *ontological* logic, not only a logic of concepts, categories, and symbols. This logic is emergent, in the sense that one speaks of the
“logic of events.” Considered in terms of its emphasis on differentiation, this logic is provocatively concrete in its relationship to abstract generalizations — hence Hegel’s seemingly
paradoxical expression “concrete universal.” Dialectic thereby
overcomes Plato’s dualistic separation of exemplary ideas from
the phenomenal world of imperfect “copies” — hence its ethical
thrust is literally structured, cumulatively as well as sequentially, in the concrete. Emerging from this superb ensemble is a
world that is always ethically problematical but also an ethics
that is always objective, a recognition of selfhood and subjectivity that embodies nonhuman and human nature, and a
development from metabolic self-maintenance to rational self-direction and innovation that locates the origins of reason *within*
nature, not in a supramundane domain *apart* from nature. The
social is thus wedded to the natural, and human reason is
wedded to nonhuman subjectivity through processes that are
richly mediated and graded in a shared continuum of development. This ecological interpretation of dialectic not only overcomes dualism but moves through differentiation away from
reductionism.
Ecology cleanses the remarkable heritage of European organismic thought of the hard teleological predeterminations it
acquired from Greek theology, the Platonistic denigration of
physicality, and the Christian preoccupation with human inwardness as “soul” and a reverence for God. Only ecology can
ventilate the dialectic as an orientation toward the objective
world by rendering it coextensive with natural evolution, a possibility that arose in the last century with the appearance of
evolutionary theory.
As such, an ecological dialectic is not solely a way of
thinking organically; it can be a source of *meaning* to natural
evolution — of ethical meaning, not only rational meaning. To
state this idea more provocatively: we cannot hope to find
humanity’s “place in nature” without knowing how it *emerged*
from nature, with all its problems and possibilities. An ecological
dialectic produces a creative paradox: second nature in an
ecological society would be the actualization of first nature’s
potentiality to achieve mind and truth. Human intellection in an
ecological society would thus “fold back” upon the evolutionary
continuum that exists in first nature. In this sense — and in this
sense alone — second nature would thus become first nature
rendered self-reflexive, a thinking nature that would know itself
and could guide its own evolution, not an unthinking nature
that “sought its own balance” through the “dynamics” of “fluctuations” and “feedback” that cause needless pain, suffering, and
death. Although thought, society, and culture would retain their
integrity, they would consciously express the abiding tendency
within first nature to press itself toward the level of conscious
self-directiveness.
In a very real sense, an ecological society would be
*a transcendence of both first nature and second nature* into a new
domain of a “free nature,” a nature that in a truly rational
humanity reached the level of conceptual thought — in short, a
nature that would willfully and thinkingly cope with conflict,
contingency, waste, and compulsion. In this new synthesis,
where first and second nature are melded into a free, rational,
and ethical nature, neither first nor second would lose its
specificity and integrity. Humanity, far from diminishing the integrity of nature, would add the dimension of freedom, reason,
and ethics to it and raise evolution to a level of self-reflexivity that
has always been latent in the emergence of the natural world.
To deny the potentiality for this transcendence and synthesis of first and second nature into a free nature is to leave
ecological thinking open to all the wayward “if-then” propositions that threaten to overrun and brutalize it. Commonsense
“brainstorms,” throwing ideas into the air with a prayer that mere
probability will provide us with a meaningful pattern, would
replace reflection and intellectual exploration.
Today, the results of this desystematized thinking are
often ludicrous when they are not simply cruel or even vicious.
If all organisms in the biosphere are “intrinsically” equally
“worthy” of a “right” to “self-realization,” as many biocentrists
believe, then human beings have no right,
*given the full logic of this proposition*, to try to stamp out mosquitoes that carry malaria
and yellow fever. Nor does the logic of this proposition give
humanity the right to eliminate the AIDS virus or other
organic sources of deadly illness.[73] It hardly helps that Bill
Devall and George Sessions, the coauthors of *Deep Ecology*,
hedged “biocentric equality” with the qualifier that “we have no
right to destroy other living beings without sufficient reason.”[74]
A loophole like “sufficient reason” is ambiguous enough to
divest the entire phrase of its logical integrity. Logic, in fact,
gives way to a purely relativistic ethics. What Devall and
Sessions consider “insufficient reason” to take a life may be very
sufficient to many other people whose well-being, indeed, whose
very survival under the present “system” depends on it. In this
kind of argumentation, which divests ethics of its social basis
and second nature of its derivation from first nature, “centricity”
bifurcates into two opposing bodies of values: a biocentrism that
makes humans and viruses equal “citizens” in a “biospheric
democracy,” and an anthropocentrism that makes humans into
self-centered sovereigns in what is presumably a biospheric
tyranny. That both views are in error is a central point in this
work. In any case, “deep ecology” taken at its word, leads us
into a foggy and dangerous logical realm from which there is
usually no recourse but Eastern mysticism.[75]
There is no “biospheric democracy” — or “tyranny,” for that
matter — in nature other than what human second nature imputes
to nonhuman first nature, just as there is no hierarchy, domination, class structure, or state in the natural world — only what the
socially conditioned human mind projects onto nonhuman
biological relationships.
“Rights,” in any meaningful sense of the word, are the
product of custom, tradition, institutional development, and social relationships, of an increasingly self-conscious historical experience, and of *mind* — that is, conceptual thought that
painstakingly formulates a constellation of rights and duties that
makes for an empathetic respect for individuals and collectivities.
They emerge from the human *social* sphere and from ways in
which human communities *institutionalize* themselves. Leopards
claim no “rights” for themselves and certainly recognize no
“right” to life, much less to “self-realization,” in the animals on
which they prey.
As mammals, these predators may be more self-aware
than, say, frogs, because of their more complex neurological and
sensory apparatus. Hence, they may be more subjective, even
more rational in a dim way. But their range of conceptualization,
from everything we know, is so limited, often so immediately
focused on their own survival needs, that to impute ethical judgments involving “rights” to them is to be truly anthropomorphic,
often without even knowing so. When biocentrists, antihumanists, and “deep ecologists” flagellate us with claims that
life-forms have “rights” to life and “self-realization” that we, as
humans, fail to recognize, they unknowingly participate in a hidden anthropomorphism that we bring to many forms of life. They
work from within human ideas and feelings — indeed, the best
that constitutes humanism — to incarnate “rights” and the notion
of a “biospheric democracy” in first nature. A human empathy
and sense of identification that yield a profound respect and sensitivity for the nonhuman world should not be confused with
sophisticated ethical “rights” and a “democracy” that have moral
and political meaning — that is, unless we are prepared to undermine the authentic social content of “rights” and “democracy” for
human society and intellection. Ironically, if there is to be anything that approximates a “biospheric democracy” in the nonhuman world, it will be shaped by human empathy, which
*presupposes* the rational and ecological intervention of human
beings into the natural world. This would entail the infusion of
human values into nature, and human mind into nonhuman
subjectivity.[76]
Biocentrists and antihumanists can hardly have their cake
and eat it too. Either humanity is a distinctive moral agent in the
biosphere, that can practice an ecological stewardship of nature — or else it is “one” with the whole world of life and simply
dissolves into it. If the latter is true, then human beings have a
“biospheric right” to use the biosphere exclusively to suit their
own ends, a “right” that cannot be denied any more than the
leopard’s “right” to kill and feast on its prey, albeit less “efficiently” than human beings. At this point, antihumanists may change
the whole level of the argument by replying that the despoliation
of the earth by plundering “humans” (whoever they may be) will
ultimately boomerang on the human species. But this turns their
argument into a pragmatic problem of a purely instrumental
character, reduces a problem in morality to a problem in engineering new technological fixes and the deployment of me
human cunning. Nature thus reverts to a Darwinian jungle that
is morally neutral at best or engaged in a duel between human
cunning and animal mindlessness at worst.
On the other hand, if we understand that human beings
are indeed moral agents because natural evolution confers upon
them a clear responsibility toward the natural world, we cannot
emphasize their unique attributes too strongly. For it is this unique
ability to think conceptually and feel a deep empathy for the
world of life that makes it possible for humanity to reverse the
devastation it has inflicted on the biosphere and create a rational
society. This implies not only that humanity, once it came into its
own humanity as the actualization of its potentialities, *could* be a
rational expression of nature’s creativity and fecundity, but that
human intervention into natural processes *could* be as creative as
natural evolution itself.
This evolutionary and dialectical viewpoint, which derive;
the human species from nature as the embodiment of nature’s
own thrust toward self-reflexivity, changes the entire argument
around competing “rights” between human and nonhuman life
forms into an exploration of the *ways* in which human beings in
tervene into the biosphere. Whether humanity recognizes that an
ecological society would be the fulfillment of a major tendency in
natural evolution, or remains blind to its own humanity as a moral
and ecological agent in nature, becomes a *social* problem that requires a social ecology. The self-effacing quietism and “spirituality”
so rampant today afflict a sizable, highly privileged sector of Euro-American society — human types so consumed by a “love” of nature and life that they may well ignore the needless but very real
suffering and pain that exist in nature and society alike.
[48] This essay was originally published in *Our Generation*, vol. 18, no. 2
(Spring-Summer 1987). It has been revised for publication here.
[49] This basically Marxian thesis, which all members of the Frankfurt School
took for granted, is repeatedly misinterpreted, particularly in the ecology
movement, when it is discussed at all. However much they opposed
domination, neither Adorno nor Horkheimer singled out hierarchy as an
underlying problematic in their writings. Indeed, their residual Marxian
premises led to a historical fatalism that saw any liberatory enterprise
(beyond art, perhaps) as hopelessly tainted by the need to dominate
nature and *consequently* “man.” This position stands completely at odds
with my own view that the notion — and no more than an *unrealizable*
notion — of dominating nature stems from the domination of human by
human. This is not a semantic difference in accounting for the origins of
domination. Like Marx, the Frankfurt School saw nature as a
“domineering” force over humanity that human guile — and class rule — had to
exorcise before a classless society was possible. The Frankfurt School, no less
than Marxism, placed the onus for domination primarily on the demanding forces of nature.
My own writings radically reverse this very traditional view of
the relationship between society and nature. I argue that the idea of
dominating nature first arose within *society* as part of its
institutionalization into gerontocracies that placed the young in varying
degrees of servitude to the old and in patriarchies that placed women in
varying degrees of servitude to men — not in any endeavor to “control”
nature or natural forces. Various modes of social institutionalization,
not modes of organizing human labor (so crucial to Marx), were the first
sources of domination, which is not to deny Marx’s thesis that class
society was economically exploitative. Hence, domination can be definitively removed only by resolving problematics that have their origins in
hierarchy and status, not in class and the technological control of nature alone.
[50] Leon E. Stover, *The Cultural Ecology of Chinese Civilization* (New York: Pica
Press, 1974).
[51] It is a compelling commentary on their naivete that Westerners can so
readily ignore oriental despotism in favor of a romantic reverence for
Asian “sages.” Chinese elites perfected an exquisitely cruel ethos toward
the masses, whom they not only exploited physically but degraded
spiritually. That this peasantry quietistically bent its head to the yoke
does not speak well for Chinese “sages.” The Tao Te Ching is an eminently political collection of passages. From the viewpoint of social ecology —
which pointedly studies the social origins of a nature ideology and
explores its logic — the passivity toward nature that the Tao Te Ching
fostered could easily have been transposed into society, just as nature
philosophy in the West has served social elites in the worst of cases, and
rebels in the best. In any case, in 1989 Chinese students exhibited more
interest in Western than Eastern ideals: they invoked ideals more
redolent of the French Revolution than the Tao Te Ching by taking to the
streets with demands for democracy and human rights.
[52] Fritjof Capra, *The Turning Point* (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1982),
pp. 286–87.
[53] Ibid., pp. 287,412.
[54] Ibid., p. 288.
[55] Ibid.
[56] See Ilya Prigogine and Isabelle Stengers, *Order Out of Chaos* (New York:
Bantam Books, 1984), pp. 291–310. The notion of the irreversibility of time,
appropriate as it may be for Prigogine to emphasize it in order to exorcise
a mechanistic dynamics based on time’s reversibility, is not congruent
with process and evolution; it is merely one presupposition of these
phenomena.
[57] That such cosmic formulas cannot explain the foundations of either organic or social development is not an argument against “foundationalism” — that is, the view that there are explanations that can
account for differentiae in the biological and social as well as the inorganic physical world. Our world has more coherence than many
relativists today are willing to admit, with its different levels of unfolding and, in their scope, different foundations, degrees of possibility, subjectivity and, with humanity, reason.
[58] Capra, *Turning Point*, p. 288.
[59] Ibid., pp. 300,393.
[60] Gregory Bateson, *Mind and Nature* (New York: E.P Dutton, 1979), p. 31.
[61] For a more complete discussion of nature’s fecundity and its source in
species variety, see my “Freedom and Necessity in Nature,” elsewhere in
this book.
[62] Human self-hatred, I may add, is not a psychological phenomenon alone;
it has ugly social roots. The privileged hate not other privileged but the
underprivileged, generally accusing them of “anthropocentric” vices and
subjecting them to the constraints of “natural law.”
[63] 16. David Foreman, interviewed by Bill Devall, “A Spanner in the Woods,”
*Simply Living*, vol. 12 (c. 1986).
[64] Let me make it clear that I believe that nature is neither hierarchical nor
egalitarian — concepts that are meaningless unless they are institutionalized socially, which presupposes a human presence in the biosphere, or
second nature. What we encounter in first nature is *complementarity*, the
mutualistic interaction of life-forms in maintaining a nonhuman ecological community. At this biological level, complementarity is not an
ethics — which is associated with reasoned behavior — but a descriptive
datum related to mutualism. I used the word *complementarity* to denote an
ethics in *The Ecology of Freedom*. Since that book was published, “natural
law” devotees have picked up on it with minimal acknowledgment and
turned it into a “law of complementarity” — a regressive use of the concept if there ever was one.
[65] I am not speaking about “dialectical materialism,” which, whatever the
intentions of Marx and Engels, used Hegelian terms and concepts to formulate what was little more than a scientistic “dialectical” mechanism.
My purpose is not to flesh out the skeleton of dialectical philosophy with
“materialism” or a latter-day nominalist physicality, but to bring nature
into the foreground of dialectical thought in an evolutionary and organismic way.
[66] G.R.G. Mure, *Aristotle* (New York: Oxford University Press, 1964), p. 7.
[67] It is arguable whether Hegel saw teleology as an inflexible predetermination of the development of the “real” in its beginnings. Hegel’s *Logic* exists on a different level from the existential reality we experience in
history and everyday life. Its “purified” categories are developed from
each other with a “logical necessity” and, in a metaphoric sense, could be
seen as a rational level parallel to the existential level from which they are
abstracted. This logos, as it were, could be taken as an exemplary and thus
inherently critical vision of the world in a highly subjectivized form
whose “logic” yields a distinct rational conclusion, just as Plato’s domain
of forms has been regarded by many Platonists as exemplary in a *normative* sense, as distinguished from the flawed world that we experience
around us.
[68] Responsibility for the confusion about the meaning of the words *real* and
actual is by no means Hegel’s but rather that of some of his translators
The German word *wirklich* has a family of English meanings that include
“real” as well as “actual.” Hegel was quite scrupulous in distinguishing
the “real” from the “actual” in his *Science of Logic*, where “reality,” as he
put it in his discussion of “Determinate Being,” seems “to be an ambiguous word,” while “Actuality is the unity of Essence and Existence.
See the Johnston and Struthers translation, *Science of Logic* (New York
Macmillan, 1929), vol. 1, p. 124, and vol. 2, p. 160. The problem arose whet
Hegel’s famous maxim, *Was vernünftig ist, das ist wirklich; und was wirklich ist, das ist vernünftig*, was mistranslated as “What is rational is real, and
what is real is rational.” The correct and philosophically meaningful
translation is “What is rational is actual, and what is actual is rational.”
The mistranslation, which rendered *real* and *actual* synonyms, conceived
the Hegelian real as the actualization of the potential. The mischief this
mistranslation produced in the interpretation of Hegel’s ideas is matched
only by the confusion it produced in the interpretation of the maxim itself. Engels, ironically, clarified Hegel’s meaning wonderfully — albeit
using *real* rather than *actual*. See his *Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of German Philosophy*, in Marx and Engels, *Selected Works* (Moscow: Progress
Publishers, 1970), vol. 3, pp. 337–38. I am not nitpicking here: the odium
that Hegelian philosophy acquired as an apologia for the Prussian state
rests in no small part on the failure to properly interpret — and translate —
this famous maxim in Hegel’s *Encyclopedia Logic* and *Philosophy of Right*.
[69] G.W.F. Hegel, *Lectures on the History of Philosophy* (New York: Humanities
Press, 1955), vol. 1, p. 22 (my emphasis). Here Hegel is describing the
dialectic in unknowing nature. “In Mind it is otherwise,” he is quick to
add; “it is consciousness and therefore it is free, uniting in itself the
beginning and the end — that is to say, intention, striving, and predetermination” (p. 22). In fact, from my viewpoint the conclusion that “Mind”
is “free” could also mean that knowing beings can be wayward,
idiosyncratic and one-sided, and — unlike nonhuman beings — cruel and,
put bluntly, evil.
[70] Unfortunately, this has not been noticed in most commentaries on
Hegel’s oeuvre, much less in philosophy generally, which seems more occupied with establishing what Heidegger means by “Being” than with
other concepts of Being in Western thought.
[71] “What-could-be,” insofar as it involves organic subjectivity and flexibility,
derives from the natural realm of potentiality. “What-should-be,” the unfolding of the rational, is an ethical extrapolation of individual and social
potentialities, of attributes of the truly self-determining person and
society.
[72] Viewed from this standpoint, there is a sense in which Hegel’s “objective
idealism” was more objective than his materialist critics realized. Possibilities — that is, the actualizations of existential potentialities — are as
objective as the inherence of an oak tree in an acorn. Ethically, this highly
illuminating approach establishes a standard of fulfillment — an objective
good, as it were — that literally informs the existential with a goal of objective fulfillment, just as we say in everyday life that an individual who
does not “live up” to his or her capabilities is an “unfulfilled” person and,
in a sense, a less than “real” person.
[73] Antihumanist “ethicists” actually take this argument seriously, I have
been startled to learn. In biocentric ethics, reports Bernard Dixon, no
“logical line can be drawn” between the conservation of whales, gentians, and flamingoes on the one hand and the conservation of
pathogenic microbes like the smallpox virus on the other, which, according to one antihumanist wag (David Ehrenfeld), is “an endangered
species.” Logical consistency requires that we try to rescue the smallpox
virus with the same ethical dedication that we bring to the survival of
whales. See Bernard Dixon, “Smallpox — Imminent Extinction, and an
Unresolved Problem,” *New Scientist*, vol. 69 (1976). For an antihumanist
position that verges on sheer misanthropy, see David Ehrenfeld, *The Arrogance of Humanism* (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978).
[74] Bill Devall and George Sessions, *Deep Ecology* (Salt Lake City: Peregrine
Smith Books, 1985), p. 67.
[75] Or else by regarding the human condition with ugly indifference.
Misanthropy, indeed an *inhumanity*, labeled biocentrism, “deep ecology,”
or population control, could provide a brutal mandate for human suffering and authoritarian state control. Ecology, on these terms, threatens to
become an ideology that is cruel, not sharing or cooperative.
[76] The more one examines the literature of biocentrists, antihumanists, and
“deep ecologists,” the more one senses manipulation. Their appeals to
human feelings like empathy and identification are translated into
“rights” that rest heavily on the historical development of humanism.
Humanism involves not simply a claim to humanity’s “superiority” over
the nonhuman world but, significantly, an appeal to human reason and a
social ethics of cooperation. Great social movements, uprisings, and
ideologies, not to speak of self-sacrificing individuals, were committed to
the achievement of these monumental goals — a history that is simply effaced from much of the biocentrist, antihumanist, and “deep ecology”
literature. Often, their place is taken by a nagging denigration of the
human spirit, decorated with metaphors lifted from Eastern philosophy.
Social analysis tends to be minimized and even deflected by a privileged
and inward concern with abstractions like “interconnectedness” and
“oneness” — in a society riven by genuine conflicts between rich and poor,
privileged and denied, and man and woman, not to speak of “deep,”
“deeper,” and the “deepest” ecologists.
** History, Civilization, and Progress:
Outline for a Criticism of Modern Relativism
*** I
Rarely have the concepts that literally define the best of Western
culture — its notions of a meaningful History, a universal Civilization, and the possibility of Progress — been called so radically into
question as they are today. In recent decades, both in the United
States and abroad, the academy and a subculture of self-styled
postmodernist intellectuals have nourished an entirely new ensemble of cultural conventions that stem from a corrosive social,
political, and moral relativism. This ensemble encompasses a
crude nominalism, pluralism, and skepticism, an extreme subjectivism, and even outright nihilism and antihumanism in various
combinations and permutations, sometimes of a thoroughly misanthropic nature. This relativistic ensemble is pitted against
coherent thought as such and against the “principle of hope” (to
use Ernst Bloch’s expression) that marked radical theory of the
recent past. Such notions percolate from so-called radical
academics into the general public, where they take the form of
personalism, amoralism, and “neoprimitivism.”
Too often in this prevailing “paradigm,” as it is frequently
called, eclecticism replaces the search for historical meaning; a
self-indulgent despair replaces hope; dystopia replaces the
promise of a rational society; and in the more sophisticated
forms of this ensemble a vaguely defined “intersubjectivity”’ — or
in its cruder forms, a primitivistic mythopoesis — replaces all
forms of reason, particularly dialectical reason. In fact, the very
concept of reason itself has been challenged by a willful antirationalism. By stripping the great traditions of Western thought
of their contours, nuances, and gradations, these relativistic
“post-historicists,” “postmodernists,” and (to coin a new word)
“post-humanists” of our day are, at best, condemning contemporary thought to a dark pessimism or, at worst, subverting it of all its meaning.
So grossly have the current critics of History, Civilization,
and Progress, with their proclivities for fragmentation and
reductionism, subverted the coherence of these basic Western
concepts that they will literally have to be defined again if they
are to be made intelligible to present and future generations.
Even more disturbingly, such critics have all but abandoned attempts to define the very concepts they excoriate. What, after
all, is *History*? Its relativistic critics tend to dissolve the concept
into eclectically assembled “histories” made up of a multiplicity
of disjointed episodes — or even worse, into myths that belong to
“different” gender, ethnic, and national groups and that they
consider to be ideologically equatable. Its nominalistic critics see
the past largely as a series of “accidents,” while its subjectivistic
critics overemphasize ideas in determining historical realities,
consisting of “imaginaries” that are essentially discontinuous
from one another. And what, after all, is *Civilization*? “Neo-primitivists” and other cultural reductionists have so blackened
the word that its rational components are now in need of a
scrupulous sorting out from the irrationalities of the past and
present. And what, finally, is *Progress*? Relativists have rejected
its aspirations to freedom in all its complexity, in favor of a
fashionable assertion of “autonomy,” often reducible to personal
proclivities. Meanwhile, antihumanists have divested the very
concept of Progress of all relevance and meaning in the farrago
of human self-denigration that marks the mood of the present
time.
A skepticism that denies any meaning, rationality,
coherence, and continuity in History, that corrodes the very existence of premises, let alone the necessity of exploring them,
renders discourse itself virtually impossible. Indeed, premises as
such have become so suspect that the new relativists regard any
attempts to establish them as evidence of a cultural pathology,
much as Freudian analysts might view a patient’s resistance to
treatment as symptomatic of a psychological pathology. Such a
psychologization of discussion closes off all further dispute. No
longer are serious challenges taken on their own terms and given
a serious response; rather, they are dismissed as symptoms of a
personal and social malaise.
So far have these tendencies been permitted to proceed
that one cannot now mount a critique of incoherence, for example, without exposing oneself to the charge of a having a
“predisposition” to “coherence” — or a “Eurocentric” bias. A
defense of clarity, equally unacceptable, invites the accusation of
reinforcing the “tyranny of reason,” while an attempt to uphold
the validity of reason is dismissed as an “oppressive” presupposition of reason’s existence. The very attempt at definition is
rejected as intellectually “coercive.” Rational discussion is impugned as a repression of nonliterate forms of “expression” suck
as rituals, howling, and dancing, or on an ostensibly philosophical scale, of intuitions, presciences, psychological motivations, of
“positional” insights that are dependent on one’s gender or ethnicity, or of revelations of one kind or another that often feed into outright mysticism.
This constellation of relativistic views, which range from
the crude to the intellectually exotic, cannot be criticized
rationally because they deny the validity of rationally independent conceptual formulations as such, presumably “constricted” by the claims of reason. For the new relativists,
“freedom” ends where claims to rationality begin — in marked
contrast to the ancient Athenians, for whom violence began
where rational discussion ended. Pluralism, the decentering of
meanings, the denial of foundations, and the hypostasization of
the idiosyncratic, of the ethically and socially contingent, and of
the psychological — all seem like part of the massive cultural
decay that corresponds to the objective decay of our era. In
American universities today, relativists in all their mutations too
often retreat into the leprous “limit experiences” of Foucault; into
a view of History as fragmentary “collective representations”
(Durkheim), “culture-patterns” (Benedict), or “imaginaries” (Castoriadis); or into the nihilistic asociality of postmodernism.
When today’s relativists do offer definitions of the concepts
they oppose, they typically overstate and exaggerate them. They
decry the pursuit of foundations — an endeavor that they have
characteristically turned into an “ism,” “foundationalism” — as
“totalistic,” without any regard for the patent need for basic principles. That foundations exist that are confined to *areas of reality*
*where their existence is valid and knowable* seems to elude these anti-foundationalists, for whom foundations must either encompass
the entire cosmos or else not exist at all. Reality would indeed be a
mystery if a few principles or foundations could encompass all
that exists, indeed, all its innovations unfolding from the subatomic realm to inorganic matter, from the simplest to the most
complex life-forms, and ultimately to the realm of astrophysics.
Some historical relativists overemphasize the subjective in
history at the expense of the material. Subjective factors certainly
do affect obviously objective developments. In the Hellenistic
Age, for example. Heron reputedly designed steam engines, yet
so far as we know they were never used to replace human labor,
as they were two thousand years later. Subjective historians, to
be sure, would emphasize the subjective factors in this fact. But
what *interaction* between ideological and material factors explains why one society — capitalism — used the steam engine on a
vast scale for the manufacture of commodities, while another —
Hellenistic society — used it merely to open temple doors for the
purposes of mass mystification? Overly subjectivistic historians
would do well to explore not only how different traditions and
sensibilities yielded these disparate uses of machines but what
*material* as well as broadly social factors either fostered or
produced them.[77]
Other historical relativists are nominalistic, overemphasizing the idiosyncratic in History, often begging basic questions that must be explored. A small group of people in ancient
Judea, we may be told, formulated a localized, ethnically based
body of monotheistic beliefs that at a chronologically later point
became the basis of the Judeo-Christian world religion. Are
these two events unrelated? Was their conjunction a mere accident? To conceive this vast development in a nominalistic way,
without probing into *why* the Roman emperors adopted the
Judeo-Christian synthesis — in an empire composed of very different cultures and languages that was direly in need of
ideological unity to prevent its complete collapse — is to produce
confusion rather than clarity.
Perhaps the most problematic aspect of relativism is its
moral arbitrariness. The moral relativism of the trite maxim
“What’s good for me is good for me, and what’s good for you is
good for you,” hardly requires elucidation.[78] In this apparently
most formless of times, relativism has left us with a solipsistic
morality and in certain subcultures a politics literally premised on
chaos. The turn of many anarchists these days toward a highly
personalistic, presumably “autonomous” subculture at the expense of responsible social commitment and action reflects, in my
view, a tragic abdication of a serious engagement in the political
and revolutionary spheres. This is no idle problem today, when
increasing numbers of people with no knowledge of History take
capitalism to be a natural, eternal social system. A politics rooted
in purely relativistic preferences, in assertions of personal
“autonomy” that stem largely from an individual’s “desire” can
yield a crude and self-serving opportunism, of a type whose
prevalence today explains many social ills. Capitalism itself, in
fact, fashioned its primary ideology on an equation of freedom
with the personal autonomy of the individual, which Anatole
France once impishly described as the “freedom” of everyone to
sleep at night under the same bridge over the Seine. Individuality
is *inseparable* from community, and autonomy is hardly meaningful unless it is embedded in a cooperative community.[79] Compared with humanity’s potentialities for freedom, a relativistic and
personalistic “autonomy” is little more than psychotherapy writ
large and expanded into a social theory.
Far too many of the relativistic critics of History, Civilization, and Progress seem less like serious social theorists than like
frightened former radical ideologues who have not fully come to
terms with the failures of the Left and of “existing socialism” in
recent years. The incoherence that is celebrated in present-day
theory is due in no small part to the one-sided and exaggerated
reaction of French academic “leftists” to the May-June events of
1968, to the behavior of the French Communist Party, and in even
greater part to the various mutations of Holy Mother Russia from
Tsarism through Stalinism to Yeltsinism. Too often, this disenchantment provides an escape route for erstwhile “revolutionaries” to ensconce themselves in the academy, to embrace
social democracy, or simply to turn to a vacuous nihilism that
hardly constitutes a threat to the existing society. From relativism,
they have constructed a skeptical barrier between themselves and
the rest of society. Yet this barrier is as intellectually fragile as the
one-sided absolutism that the Old Left tried to derive from Hegel,
Marx, and Lenin.
Fairness requires me to emphasize that contrary to the
conventional wisdom about the Left today, there has never been
any “existing socialism,” the erstwhile claims of Eastern European leaders to have achieved it notwithstanding. Nor was Hegel
a mere teleologist; nor Marx a mere “productivist”; nor Lenin the
ideological “father” of the ruthless opportunist and counterrevolutionary, Stalin.[80] In reaction to the nightmare of the “Soviet”
system, today’s relativists have not only overreacted to and exaggerated the shortcomings of Hegel, Marx, and Lenin; they have
concocted an ideological prophylaxis to protect themselves from
the still-unexorcised demons of a tragically failed past instead of
formulating a credible philosophy that can address the problems
that now confront us at all levels of society and thought.
Current expositions of oxymoronic “market socialisms”
and “minimal statisms” by “neo-” and “post-Marxists suggest
where political relativism and assertions of “autonomy” can lead
us.[81] Indeed, it is quite fair to ask whether today’s fashionable
political relativism itself would provide us with more than a
paper-thin obstacle to totalitarianism. The dismissal of attempts to
derive continuity in History, coherence in Civilization, and meaning in Progress as evidence of a “totalizing” or “totalitarian” mentality in pursuit of all-encompassing foundations directly or
indirectly imbricates reason, particularly that of the Enlightenment era, with totalitarianism, and even significantly *trivializes*
the harsh reality and pedigree of totalitarianism itself. In fact, the
actions of the worst totalitarians of our era, Stalin and Hitler, were
guided less by the objectively grounded principles or “foundational” ideas they so cynically voiced in public than by a kind of
relativistic or situational ethics. For Stalin, who was no more a
“socialist” or “communist” than he was an “anarchist” or
“liberal,” theory was merely an ideological fig leaf for the concentration of power. To overlook Stalin’s sheer opportunism is
myopic at best and cynical at worst. Under his regime, only a
hopelessly dogmatic “Communist” who had managed to negotiate and survive Stalin’s various changes in the “party line”
could have taken Stalin seriously as a “Marxist-Leninist.” Hitler,
in turn, exhibited amazing flexibility in bypassing ideology for
strictly pragmatic ends. In his first months in power, he decimated
all the “true believers” of National Socialism among his storm
troopers at the behest of the Prussian officer caste, which feared
and detested the Nazi rabble.
In the absence of an objective grounding — notably, the
very real human potentialities that have been formed by the
natural, social, moral, and intellectual development of our
species — notions like freedom, creativity, and rationality are
reduced to “intersubjective” relations, underpinned by personal
and individualistic preferences (nothing more!) that are
“resolved” by another kind of tyranny — notably, the tyranny of
consensus. Lacking foundations of any kind, lacking any real
form and solidity, notions of “intersubjectivity” can be frighteningly homogenizing because of their seemingly “democratic”
logic of consensuality — a logic that precludes the dissensus and
ideological dissonance so necessary for stimulating innovation.
In the consensual “ideal speech situation” that Jurgen Habermas
deployed to befog the socialist vision of the 1970s, this “intersubjectivity,” a transcendental “Subject” or “Ego” like a mutated
Rousseauian “General Will,” replaces the rich elaboration of
reason. Today this subjectivism or “intersubjectivity” — be it in
the form of Habermas’s neo-Kantianism or Baudrillard’s
egoism — lends itself to a notion of “social theory” as a matter of
personal taste. Mere constructions of “socially conditioned”
human minds, free-floating in a sea of relativism and ahistoricism, reject a potential objective ground for freedom in the in
terests of avoiding “totalitarian Totalities” and the “tyranny” of
an “Absolute.” Indeed, *reason itself* is essentially reduced to
“intersubjectivity.” Juxtaposed with literary celebrations of the
“subjective reason” of personalism, and its American sequelae of
mysticism, individual redemption, and conformity, and its post-
1968 French sequelae of postmodernist, psychoanalytic, relativist,
and neo-Situationist vagaries, Marx’s commitment to thorough
thinking would be attractive.
Ideas that are objectively grounded, unlike those that are
relativistically asserted, can provide us with a *definable* body of
principles with which we can seriously grapple. The foundational coherence and, in the best of cases, the rationality of objectively
grounded views at least make them explicit and tangible and free
them from the vagaries of the labyrinthine personalism so very
much in vogue today. Unlike a foundationless subjectivism that is
often reducible, under the rubric of “autonomy,” to personal
preferences, objective foundations are at least subject to challenges in a *free* society. Far from precluding rational critique, they invite it. Far from taking refuge in an unchallengeable nominalist
elusiveness, they open themselves to the test of coherence. Paul
Feyerabend’s corrosive (in my view, cynical) relativism to the contrary notwithstanding, the natural sciences in the past three centuries have been among the most emancipatory human endeavors in the history of ideas — partly because of their pursuit of
unifying or foundational explanations of reality.[82] In the end,
what should always be of concern to us is the *content* of objective
principles, be they in science, social theory, or ethics, not a flippant condemnation of their claims to coherence and objectivity per se.
Indeed, despite claims to the contrary, relativism has its
own hidden “foundations” and metaphysics. As such, because its
premises are masked, it may well produce an ideological tyranny
far more paralyzing than the “totalitarianism” that it imputes to
objectivism and an expressly *reasoned* “foundationalism “ Insofar
as our concerns should center on the *bases* of freedom and the *nature* of reason, modern relativism has “decentered” these crucial
issues into wispy expressions of personal faith in an atmosphere
of general skepticism. We may choose to applaud the relativist
who upholds his or her strictly personal faith by reiterating
Luther’s defiant words at Worms, *Hier stehe ich, ich kann nicht anders*
(“Here I stand, I cannot do otherwise”). But to speak frankly, unless we also hear a rational argument to validate that stand,
one based on more than a subjective inclination, who gives a
damn about this resolve?
*** II
Which again raises the problem of what History, Civilization, and
Progress actually are.
History, I wish to contend, is the rational content and
continuity of events (with due regard for qualitative “leaps”)
that are grounded in humanity’s potentialities for freedom,
self-consciousness, and cooperation, in the self-formative
development of increasingly libertarian forms of consociation. It is the rational “infrastructure,” so to speak, that
coheres human actions and institutions over the past and the
present in the direction of an emancipatory society and emancipated individuals. That is to say. History is precisely what is *rational* in human development. It is what is rational, moreover, in
the *dialectical* sense of the implicit that unfolds, expands, and
begins in varying degrees through increasing differentiation to
actualize humanity’s very *real* potentialities for freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation.[83]
It will immediately be objected that irrational events, unrelated to this actualization, explode upon us at all times, in all eras
and cultures. But insofar as they defy rational interpretation, they
remain precisely *events*, not History, however consequential their
effects may be on the course of other events. Their impact may be
very powerful, to be sure, but they are not dialectically rooted in
humanity’s potentialities for freedom, self-consciousness, and
cooperation.[84] They can be assembled into *Chronicles*, the stuff out
of which Froissart constructed his largely anecdotal “histories,”
but not History in the sense I am describing. Events may even
“overtake History,” so to speak, and ultimately submerge it in the
irrational and the evil. But without an increasingly self-reflexive
History, which present-day relativism threatens to extinguish, we
would not even know that it had happened.
If we deny that humanity has these potentialities for
freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation — conceived as one
ensemble — then along with many self-styled “socialists” and
even former anarchists like Daniel Cohn-Bendit, we may well
conclude that “capitalism has won,” as one disillusioned friend
put it; that “history” has reached its terminus in “bourgeois
democracy” (however tentative this “terminus” may actually be);
and that rather than attempt to enlarge the realm of the rational
and the free, we would do best to ensconce ourselves in the lap of
capitalism and make it as comfortable a resting place as possible
for ourselves.
As a mere adaptation to what exists, to the “what-is,” such
behavior is merely animalistic. Sociobiologists may even regard it
as genetically unavoidable. But my critics need not be sociobiologists to observe that the historical record exhibits a great
deal of adaptation and worse — of irrationality and violence, of
pleasure in the destruction of oneself and others — and to question my assertion that History is the unfolding of human potentialities for freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation. Indeed,
humans have engaged in destruction and luxuriated in real and
imaginary cruelties toward one another that have produced hells
on earth. They have created the monstrosities of Hitler’s death
camps and Stalin’s gulags, not to speak of the mountains of
skulls that Mongol and Tartar invaders of Eurasia left behind in
distant centuries. But this record hardly supplants a dialectic of
unfolding and maturing of potentialities in social development,
nor is the *capacity* of humans to inflict cruelties on each other
equivalent to their *potentialities* for freedom, self-consciousness,
and cooperation.
Here, human capacities and human potentialities must be
distinguished from each other. The human capacity for inflicting
injury belongs to the realm of natural history, to what humans
share with animals in the biological world or “first nature.” First
nature is the domain of survival, of core feelings of pain and fear,
and in that sense our behavior remains animalistic, which is by
no means altered with the emergence of social or “second nature.”
*Unknowing* animals merely try to survive and adapt to one
degree or another to the world in which they exist. By contrast.
humans are animals of a very *special* kind; they are *knowing*
animals, they have the intelligence to calculate and to devise,
even in the service of needs that they share with nonhuman life-forms. Human reason and knowledge have commonly served
aims of self-preservation and self-maximization by the use of a
formal logic of expediency, a logic that rulers have deployed for
social control and the manipulation of society. These methods
have their roots in the animal realm of simple means-ends
choices to survive.
But humans also have the *capacity* to *deliberately* inflict pain
and fear, to use their reason for perverse passions, in order to
coerce others or merely for cruelty for its own sake. Only *knowing*
animals, ironically capable of intelligent innovation, with the
*Schadenfreude* to enjoy vicariously the torment of others, can inflict fear and pain in a coldly calculated or even passionate manner. The Foucauldian hypostasization of the body as the “terrain”
of sado-masochistic pleasure can be easily elaborated into a
metaphysical justification of violence, depending, to be sure, on
what “pleases” a particular perpetrating ego.[85] In this sense,
human beings are too intelligent *not* to live in a rational society,
*not* to live within institutions formed by reason and ethics that
restrict their capacity for irrationality and violence.[86] Insofar as
they do not, humans remain dangerously wayward and unformed creatures with enormous powers of destruction as well as creation.
Humanity may have a “potentiality for evil,” as one colleague has argued. But that over the course of social development
people have exhibited an explosive capacity to perpetrate the
most appallingly evil acts does not mean that human potentiality
is constituted to produce evil and a nihilistic destructiveness. The
capacity of certain Germans to establish an Auschwitz, indeed the
means and the goal to exterminate a whole people in a terrifyingly industrial manner, was inherent neither in Germany’s development nor in the development of industrial rationalization as such.
However anti-Semitic many Germans were over the previous two
centuries. Eastern Europeans were equally or even more so; ironically, industrial development in Western Europe may have done
more to achieve Jewish juridical emancipation in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries than all the Christian pieties that marked
preindustrial life during the Middle Ages. Indeed, evil may have a
“logic” — that is to say, it may be explained. But most general accounts explain the evolution of evil in terms of adventitious evil
acts and events, if this can be regarded as explanation at all.
Hitler’s takeover of Germany, made possible more by economic
and political dislocations than by the racial views he espoused,
was precisely a terrible *event* that cannot be explained in terms of
any human potentiality for evil. The horror of Auschwitz lies almost as much in its *inexplicability*, in its appallingly extraordinary
character, as in the monstrosities that the Nazis generally inflicted
on European Jews. It is in this sense that Auschwitz remains
hauntingly *inhuman* and that it has tragically produced an abiding mistrust by many people of Civilization and Progress.
When explanations of evil are not merely narrations
of events, they explain evil in terms of instrumental or conventional logic. The knowing animal, the human being, who is viciously harmful, does not use the developmental reason of dialectic, the reason of ethical reflection; nor a coherent, reflective
reason, grounded in a knowledge of History and Civilization; nor
even the knowing of an ambiguous, arbitrary, self-generated “imaginary,” or a morality of personal taste and pleasure. Rather, the
knowing animal uses instrumental calculation to serve evil ends,
including the infliction of pain.
The very existence of irrationalism and evil in many social
phenomena today compels us to uphold a clear standard of the
“rational” and the “good” by which to judge the one against the
other. A purely personalistic, relativistic, or functional approach
will hardly do for establishing ethical standards — as many
critiques of subjectivism and subjective reason have shown. The
personal tastes from which subjectivism and relativism derive
their ethical standards are as transient and fleeting as moods.
Nor will a nominalistic approach suffice: to reduce History to an
incomprehensible assortment of patterns or to inexplicable
products of the imagination is to deny social development all internal *ethical* coherence.[87] Indeed, an unsorted, ungraded, unmediated approach reduces our understanding of History to a
crude eclecticism rather than an insightful coherence, to an overemphasis on differentiae (so easy to do, these mindless days!)
and the idiosyncratic rather than the meaningful and the universal, more often attracting the commonsensical individual to the
psychoanalytic couch than helping him or her reconstitute a left
libertarian social movement.
If our views of social development are to be structured
around the *differences* that distinguish one culture or period from
another, we will ignore underlying tendencies that, with extraordinary universality, have greatly expanded the material and. cultural conditioi’is for freedom on various levels of individual and
social self-understanding. By grossly emphasizing disjunctions,
social isolates, unique configurations, and chance events, we will
reduce shared, clearly common social developments to an archipelago of cultures, each essentially unrelated to those that preceded and followed it. Yet many historical forces have
emerged, declined, and emerged again, despite the formidable
obstacles that often seemed to stand in their way. One does not
have to explain “everything” in “foundational” terms to recognize the existence of *abiding* problems such as scarcity, exploitation, class rule, domination, and hierarchy that have agonized
oppressed peoples for thousands of years.[88] If critics were correct
in dubbing dialectic a mystery for claiming to encompass *all* —
phenomena by a few cosmic formulas, then they would be
obliged to regard human social development as a mystery if they
claimed that it lacks any continuity and unity — that is, the bases
for a philosophy of History. Without a notion of continuity in
History, how can we explain the extraordinary efflorescence of
culture and technique that *Homo sapiens sapiens* produced during
the Magdelenian period, some twenty or thirty thousand years
ago? How can we explain the clearly unrelated evolution of complex agricultural systems in at least three separate parts of the
world — the Middle East, Southeast Asia, and Mesoamerica — that
apparently had no contact with one another and that were based
on the cultivation of very different grains, notably wheat, rice,
and maize? How can we explain the great gathering of social
forces in which, after ten thousand years of arising, stagnating,
and disappearing, cities finally gained control over the agrarian
world that had impeded their development, yielding the “urban
revolution,” as V. Gordon Childe called it, in different areas of the
world that could have had no contact with one another?
Mesoamerica and Mesopotamia, most clearly, could not
have had any contact with each other since Paleolithic times, yet
their agriculture, towns and cities, literacy, and mathematics
developed in ways that are remarkably similar. Initially
Paleolithic foragers, both produced highly urbanized cultures
based on grain cultivation, glyphs, accurate calendrics, and very
elaborate pottery, to cite only the most striking parallels. The
wheel was known to Mesoamericans, although they do not seem
to have used it, probably for want of appropriate draft animals, as
well as the zero, despite the absence of any communication with
Eurasian societies. It requires an astonishing disregard for the
unity of Civilization on the part of historical relativists to emphasize often minor differences, such as clothing, some daily customs, and myths, at the expense of a remarkable unity of
consciousness and social development that the two cultures exhibited on two separate continents after many millennia of isolation from each other.
The unity of social evolution is hardly vitiated by such
nominalistic perplexities as “Why didn’t a Lenin appear in Germany rather than Russia in 1917–1918?” In view of the great *tidal*
movements of History, it might be more appropriate to explore —
Lenin’s strong will and Kerensky’s psychological flaccidity
aside — whether the traditional proletariat was *ever* capable of
creating a “workers’ state,” indeed, what that statist concept really meant when working men and women were obliged to devote
the greater amount of their lives to arduous labor at the expense
of their participation in managing social affairs. Caprice, accident, irrationality, and “imaginaries” certainly enter into social
development for better or worse. But they literally have no meaning if there is no ethical standard by which to define the other
of what we are presupposing with our standard.[89] Seemingly accidental or eccentric factors must be raised to the level of *social theory* rather than shriveled to the level of nominalistic minutiae
if we are to understand them.
Despite the accidents, failures, and other aberrations that
can alter the course of *rational* social and individual development,
there is a “*legacy of freedom*,” as I named a key chapter in my book
*The Ecology of Freedom*, a tradition of increasing approximation of
humanity toward freedom and self-consciousness, in ideas and
moral values and the overall terrain of social life. Indeed, the existence of History as a coherent unfolding of real emancipatory
potentialities is clearly verified by the existence of *Civilization*, the
potentialities of History embodied and partially actualized. It
consists of the concrete advances, material as well as cultural and
psychological, that humanity *has* made toward greater degrees of
freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation, as well as rationality itself. To have transcended the limitations of the kinship tie;
to have gone beyond mere foraging into agriculture and industry; to have replaced the parochial band or tribe with the increasingly universal city; to have devised writing, produced
literature, and developed richer forms of expression than non-literate peoples could have ever imagined — all of these and many
more advances have provided the conditions for evolving increasingly sophisticated notions of individuality and expanding
notions of reason that remain stunning achievements to this very day.
It is dialectical reason rather than conventional reason
that apprehends the development of this tradition. Indeed,
dialectical logic can hardly be treated coequally with eruptions
of brutality, however calculated they may be, since in no sense
can *episodic capacities* be equated with an *unfolding potentiality*. A
dialectical understanding of History apprehends differentiae in
quality, logical continuity, and maturation in historical development, as distinguished from the kinetics of mere change or a
simple directivity of “social dynamics.” Rarefying projects for
human liberation to the point that they are largely subjective
“imaginaries,” without relevance to the realities of the overall
human experience and the insights of speculative reason, can
cause us to overlook the existential impact of these developments
and the promise they hold for ever-greater freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation. We take these achievements all
too easily for granted without asking what kind of human beings
we would be if they had not occurred as a result of historical and
cultural movements more fundamental than eccentric factors.
These achievements, let us acknowledge quite clearly, *are*
Civilization, indeed a civilizing continuum that is nonetheless infused by terribly barbaric, indeed animalistic features. The
civilizing process has been ambiguous, as I have emphasized in
my “Ambiguities of Freedom,”[90] but it has nonetheless historically
turned folk into citizens, while the process of environmental
adaptation that humans share with animals has been transformed into a wide-ranging, strictly human process of *innovation*
in distinctly alterable environments.[91] It is a process that reached
its greatest universality, *primarily* in Europe, however much other
parts of the world have fed into the experience. Those of us who
understandably fear that the barrier between Civilization and
chaos is fragile actually *presuppose* the existence of Civilization,
not simply of chaos, and the *existence* of rational coherence, not
simply of irrational incoherence.
Moreover, the dialectic of freedom has emerged again and
again in *recurring struggles for freedom*, ideological as well as physical, that have abidingly *expanded* overall goals of freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation — as much in social evolution as a
whole as within specific temporal periods. The past is replete
with instances in which masses of people, however disparate
their cultures, have tried to resolve the same millennia-old
problems in remarkably similar ways and with remarkably
similar views. The famous cry for equality that the English
peasants raised in their 1381 revolt — “When Adam delved and
Eve span, who was then the gentleman?” — is as meaningful for
contemporary revolts as it was six hundred years ago, in a world
that presumably had a far different “imaginary” from our own.
The denial of a rational universal History, of Civilization, of
Progress, and of social *continuity* renders any historical *perspective*
impossible and hence any revolutionary praxis meaningless except as a matter of personal, indeed often *very* personal, taste.
Even as social movements attempt to attain what they
might call a rational society, in developing humanity’s potentialities for freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation. History
may constitute itself as an ever-developing “whole.” This whole, I
should emphasize, must be distinguished from a terminal
Hegelian “Absolute” just as demands for coherence in a body of
views must be distinguished from the worship of such an “Absolute” and just as the capacity of speculative reason to educe in a
dialectically logical manner the *very real potentialities* of humanity
for freedom is neither teleological nor absolutist, much less
“totalitarian.”[92] There is nothing teleological, mystical, or absolutist about History. “Wholeness” is no teleological referent,
whose evolving components are merely parts of a predetermined
“Absolute.” Neither the rational unfolding of human potentialities nor their actualization in an eternally given “Totality” is predestined.
Nor is the working out of our potentialities some vague
sort of suprahuman activity. Human beings are not the passive
tools of a Spirit (*Geist*) that works out its complete and final self-realization and self-consciousness. Rather, they are *active agents*,
the authentic “constituents” of History, who may or may not
elaborate their potentialities in social evolution. Aborted the
revolutionary tradition has been here, and discontinuous it has
been there — and for all we know it may ultimately be aborted for
humanity as such. Whether an “ultimate” rational society will
even exist as a liberatory “end of history” is beyond anyone’s
predictive powers. We cannot say what the scope of a rational,
free, and cooperative society would be, let alone presume to claim
knowledge of its “limits.” Indeed, insofar as the historical process
effected by living human agents is likely to expand our notions of
the rational, the democratic, the free, and the cooperative, it is undesirable to dogmatically assert that they have any finality. History forms its own ideal of these notions at various times, which
in turn have been expanded and enriched.
Every society has the possibility of attaining a remarkable
degree of rationality, given the material, cultural, and intellectual
conditions that allow for it or, at least, are available to it. Within
the limits of a slave, patriarchal, warrior, and urban world, for example, the ancient Athenian *polis* functioned *more* rationally than
Sparta or other Greek *poleis*. It is precisely the task of speculative
reason to educe *what should exist* at any given period, based on the
very real potentialities for the expansion of these notions. To conclude that “the end of history” has been attained in liberal
capitalism would be to jettison the historical legacy of these magnificent efforts to create a free society — efforts that claimed
countless lives in the great revolutions of the past. For my part, I
and probably many revolutionaries today want no place in such
an “end of history”; nor do I want to forget the great emancipatory movements for popular freedom in all their many forms that occurred over the ages.
History, Civilization, and Progress are the *dialectically rational* social dispensations that form, even with all the impediments they face, a dialectical legacy of freedom. The existence of
this legacy of freedom in no way denies the existence of a “legacy
of domination,”[93] which remains within the realm of the irrational. Indeed, these “legacies” intertwine with and condition each
other. Human ideals, struggles, and achievements of various approximations to freedom cannot be separated from the cruelties
and barbarities that have marked social development over the centuries, often giving rise to new social configurations whose
development is highly unpredictable. But a crucial historical
problematic remains, to the extent that reason can foresee a given
development: will it be freedom or domination that is nourished? I
submit that *Progress* is the advance — and as everyone presumably
hopes, the ascendancy — of freedom over domination, which clearly cannot be conceptually frozen in an ahistorical eternity, given
the growing awareness of both hopes and oppressions that have
come to light in only a few recent generations. Progress also appears in the overall improvement, however ambiguous, of
humanity’s material conditions of life, the emergence of a rational
ethics, with enlightened standards of sensibility and conduct, out
of unreflexive custom and theistic morality, and social institutions
that foster continual self-development and cooperation. However
lacking our ethical claims in relation to social practice may be,
given all the barbarities of our time, we now subject brutality to
much harsher judgments than was done in earlier times.[94]
It is difficult to conceive of a rational ethics — as distinguished from unthinking custom and mere commandments of
morality, like the Decalogue — without *reasoned* criteria of good
and evil based on real potentialities for freedom that speculative
reason can educe *beyond a given reality*. The “sufficient conditions”
for an ethics must be explicated rationally, not simply affirmed in
public opinion polls, plebiscites, or an “intersubjective” consensus that fails to clarify what constitutes “subjectivity” and
“autonomy” Admittedly, this is not easy to do in a world that
celebrates vaporous words, but it is necessary to discover truth
rather than work with notions that stem from the conventional
“wisdom” of our times. As Hegel insisted, even commonplace
moral maxims like “Love thy neighbor as thyself” raise many
problems, such as what we really mean by “love.”
*** III
I believe that we lack an adequate Left critique of the theoretical
problems raised by classical Hegelianism, Marxism, anarchism, social democracy, and liberalism, with the result that there are
serious lacunae in the critical exploration of these “isms.” A comprehensive critical exploration would require an analysis not only
of the failings of the subject matter under discussion, but of the
hidden presuppositions of the critic. The critic would be obliged to
clearly define what he or she *means* by the concepts he or she is
using. This self-reflexive obligation cannot be bypassed by substituting undertheorized terms like “creativity,” “freedom,” and
“autonomy” for in-depth analysis. The complexity of these ideas,
their sweep, the traditions that underpin and divide them against
one another, and the ease with which they can be abused and, in
the academic milieux in which they are bandied around, detached
from the lived material and social conditions of life — all require
considerable exploration.
Among the important concepts and relationships that require elucidation is the tendency to reduce objectivity to the
natural law” of physical science.[95] In the conventional scientific
sense of the term, “natural law” preordains the kinetic future of
objects colliding with each other. It may even preordain what an
individual plant will become under the normal conditions required for its growth. Objectivity, however, has a multiplicity of
meanings and does not necessarily correspond to the “laws” that
the natural sciences seek to formulate. It involves not only the
materiality of the world in a broad sense but also its *potentialities*,
as very real but as yet unrealized form structured to undergo
elaboration. The evolution of key life-forms toward ever-greater
subjectivity, choice, and behavioral flexibility — *real* potentialities
and their degrees of actualization — and toward human intellectuality, language, and social institutionalization, is transparently
clear. An objective potentiality is the *implicit* that may or may not
be actualized, depending upon the conditions in which it emerges. Among humans, the actualization of potentiality is not *necessarily* restricted by anything besides aging and death, although it
is not free to unfold unconditionally. Minimally, the actualization
of humanity’s potentialities consists in its attainment of a rational
society. Such a society, of course, would not appear *ab novo*. By its
very nature it would require development, maturation, or, more
precisely, a History — a rational development that may be fulfilled
by the very fact that the society is potentially constituted to be
rational. If the self-realization of life in the nonhuman world is
survival or stability, the self-realization of humanity is the degree
of freedom, self-consciousness, and cooperation, as well as
rationality in society. Reduced merely or primarily to scientific
“natural law,” objectivity is highly attenuated. It does not encompass potentiality and the working of the dialectic in existential
reality, let alone its presence as a standard for gauging reality
against actuality in the unfolding of human phenomena.[96]
Marx’s claim to have unearthed “the natural laws of
capitalist production” was absurd, but to advance relativism as
an alternative to it is equally absurd. A younger, more flexible
Marx insightfully claimed, “It is not enough that thought should
seek its actualization; actuality itself must strive toward
thought.”[97] Thought, qua dialectical reason, becomes transformative in shaping the present and the future insofar as human
rational praxis objectively actualizes the implicit. Today, when
subjectivism reigns supreme and the common response even to
significant events is to erase any meaning and coherence from
History, Civilization, and Progress, there is a desperate need for
an objectivity that is immensely broader than natural science and
“natural laws,” on the one hand, and an emphasis on the
idiosyncratic, “imaginary,” and adventitious, on the other. If vulgar Marxists used “science” to turn the *ethical* claim that
“socialism is necessary” into the *teleological* assertion that
“socialism is inevitable,” today’s “post-Marxist” critics repeat a
similar vulgarity by mordantly celebrating incoherence in the
realm of social theory. The claim of socialism’s inevitability was
crudely deterministic; the claim of its necessity was a rational
and ethical explication.
“Intersubjectivity” and “intersubjective relations,” for their
part, cannot explain in any meaningful way *how* humanity is
rooted in biological evolution, or what we broadly call “Nature,”
least of all by deftly using the phrase “social construction” to
bypass the very objective evolutionary reality that “Nature” connotes. Just as a subjectivized nexus of “intersubjective relations”
dissolves the objectivity of social phenomena, so a subjectivized
nexus of “social construction” dissolves the objectivity of natural
evolution, as if neither social phenomena nor natural evolution
had any actuality, aside from being a pair of simplistic epistemological categories. Here Kant reappears with a vengeance,
with the possible difference that even his noumenal or unknowable external reality has disappeared.
Dialectic, it should be emphasized, cannot be reduced
merely to a “method” on the grounds that such disparate dialectical thinkers as Aristotle, John Scotus Eriugena, Hegel, and Marx
comprehended different realms of knowledge and reality in different ways and periods. Humanity’s knowledge of dialectic
*has itself been a process*, and dialectical thinking has itself undergone
development — a *cumulative* development, not a so-called “paradigm shift” — just as scientists have been obliged in the give-and-take or sublation of ideas to resolve one-sided insights into the
nature of reality and its becoming.[98]
Although the broader objectivity that dialectical reasoning
educes does not dictate that reason *will* prevail, it implies that it
*should* prevail, thereby melding ethics with human activity and
creating the basis for a truly objective ethical socialism or anarchism. As such, dialectic is not simply an ontological causality;
*it is also an ethics* — an aspect of dialectical philosophy that has not
been sufficiently emphasized. Dialectical reason permits an
ethics in history by upholding the rational influence of “what-should-be” as against “what-is.” History, qua the dialectically rational, exercises a pressing claim, so to speak, on our canons of
behavior and our interpretation of events. Without this
liberatory legacy and a human practice that fosters its unfolding,
we have absolutely no basis for even *judging* what is creative or
stagnant, rational or irrational, or good or evil in any constellation of cultural phenomena other than personal preference. Unlike science’s limited objectivity, dialectical naturalism’s
objectivity is ethical *by its very nature*, by virtue of the kind of
society it identifies as rational, a society that is the actualization
of humanity’s potentialities.[99] It sublates science’s narrow
objectivity to advance, by rational inferences drawn from the objective nature of human potentialities, a society that increasingly
actualizes those potentialities. And it does so on the basis of what
*should be* as the fulfillment of the rational, that is to say, on rational knowledge of the good and a conceptual congruence between the good and the socially rational that can be embodied in free
institutions.
It is not that social development is dialectical because it is
*necessarily* rational, as a traditional Hegelian might suppose, but
rather that where social development *is* rational, it is dialectical or
historical. We aver, in short, that we can educe from a uniquely
human potentiality a rational development that advances human
self-realization in a free, self-conscious, and cooperative society.
Speculative reason here stakes out a claim to discern the rational
development (by no means immune to irrational vicissitudes) of
society as it *should be* — given human potentiality, as we know it in
real life, to evolve from a tribal folk to a democratic citizenry, from
mythopoesis to reason, from the submission of personhood in a
folklike collectivity to individuality in a rational community — all
as rational ends as well as existential realities. Speculative reason
should always be called upon to understand and *explain* not only
what has happened with respect to these problematics but *why*
they recur in varying degrees and how they can be resolved.
In a very real sense, the past fifteen or more years hava
been remarkably *ahistorical*, albeit highly *eventful*, insofar as they
have not been marked by any lasting advance toward a rational
society. Indeed, if anything, they would seem to be tilting
toward a regression, ideologically and structurally, to barbarism,
despite spectacular advances in technology and science, whose
outcome we cannot foresee. There cannot be a dialectic, however, that deals “dialectically” with the irrational, with regression into barbarism — that is to say, a strictly negative dialectics.
Both Adorno’s book of that name and Horkheimer and Adorno’s
*The Dialectic of Enlightenment*, which traced the “dialectical” descent of reason (in Hegel’s sense) into instrumentalism, were little more than mixed farragoes of convoluted neo-Nietzschean
verbiage, often brilliant, colorful, and excitingly informative,
but often confused, rather dehumanizing and, to speak bluntly,
irrational.[100] A “dialectic” that lacks *any* spirit of transcendence
(*Aufhebung*) and denies the “negation of the negation” is
spurious at its very core.[101] One of the earliest attempts to
“dialectically” deal with social regression was the little-known
“retrogression thesis,” undertaken by Josef Weber, the German
Trotskyist theorist who was the exile leader of the Internationale
Kommunisten Deutschlands (IKD). Weber authored the IKD’s
program, “Capitalist Barbarism or Socialism,” published in
November 1944 in Max Schachtman’s *New International* during
the bitterest days of the Second World War and posed the question that many thinking revolutionaries of that distant era faced:
what forms would capitalism take *if* the proletariat failed to
make a socialist revolution after the Second World War?[102] As the
title of the IKD document suggests, not all Marxists, perhaps
fewer than we may think, regarded socialism as “inevitable” or
thought that there would necessarily be a socialist “end to history” after the war. Indeed, many whom I knew as a dissident
Trotskyist fifty years ago were convinced that barbarism was as
serious a danger for the future as socialism was its greatest
hope.[103] The prospect of barbarism that we face today may differ
in form from what revolutionary Marxists faced two generations
ago, but it does not differ in kind. The future of Civilization is
still very much in the balance, and the very memory of alternative emancipatory visions to capitalism are becoming dimmer with each generation.
Although the “imaginary” and subjective are certainly elements in social development, contemporary capitalism is steadily
dissolving the uniqueness of “imaginaries” of earlier, more
diverse cultures. Indeed, capitalism is increasingly leveling and
homogenizing society, culturally and economically, to a point
that the same commodities, industrial techniques, social institutions, values, even desires, are being “universalized” to an unprecedented degree in humanity’s long career. At a time when
the mass-manufactured commodity has become a fetish more
potent than any archaic fetish that early cultures “imagined”;
when the glossy tie and three-piece suit are replacing traditional
sarongs, cloaks, and shoulder capes; when the word *business* requires fewer and fewer translations in the world’s diverse
vocabularies; and when English has become the lingua franca
not only of so-called “educated classes” but people in ordinary
walks of life (need I add more to this immensely long list?), it is
odd that the idiosyncratic in various cultural constellations is
now acquiring a significance in academic discourse that it rarely
attained in the past. This discourse may be a way of side-stepping
a much-needed examination of the challenges posed by recent
capitalist developments, and instead mystifying them in convoluted discussions that fill dense academic tomes and, particularly in the case of Foucault and postmodernism, satisfying
the “imaginaries” of self-centered individuals, for whom the
spray paint can has become the weapon of choice with which to
assault the capitalist system and a hairstyle the best way to affront the conventional petty bourgeoisie.
Stated bluntly: no *revolutionary* movement can grow if its
theorists essentially deny Bloch’s “principle of hope,” which the
movement so needs for an inspired belief in the future; if it denies
universal History that affirms sweeping common problems that
have besieged humanity over the ages; if it denies the shared interests that give a movement the basis for a common struggle in
achieving a rational dispensation of social affairs; if it denies a
processual rationality and a growing idea of the Good based on
more than personalis tic (or “intersubjective” and “consensual”)
grounds; if it denies the powerful civilizatory dimensions of social development (ironically, dimensions that are in fact so useful
to contemporary nihilists in criticizing humanity’s failings); and
if it denies historical Progress. Yet in present-day theoretics, a
series of events replaces History, cultural relativism replaces
Civilization, and a basic pessimism replaces a belief in the possibility of Progress. What is more sinister, mythopoesis replaces
reason, and dystopia the prospect of a rational society. What is at
stake in all these displacements is an intellectual and practical
regression of appalling proportions — an especially alarming
development today, when theoretical clarity is of the utmost
necessity. What our times require is a *social* analysis that calls for a
revolutionary and ultimately popular movement, not a psycho-analysis that issues self-righteous disclaimers for “beautiful
souls,” ideologically dressed in cloaks of personal virtue.
Given the disparity between what rationally *should be* and
what currently *exists*, reason may not necessarily become embodied in a free society. If and when the realm of freedom ever
does reach its most expansive form, to the extent that we can envision it, and if hierarchy, class, domination, and exploitation
were ever abolished, we would be obliged to enter that realm
only as *free beings*, as truly rational, ethical, and empathetic
“knowing animals,” with the highest intellectual insight and ethical probity, not as brutes coerced into it by grim necessity and
fear. The riddle of our times is whether today’s relativists would
have equipped us intellectually and ethically to cross into that
most expansive realm of freedom. We cannot merely be *driven*
into greater freedom by blind forces that we fail to understand, as
Marxists implied, still less by mere *preferences* that have no standing in anything more than an “imaginary,” “instincts,” or libidinal “desires.”[104]
The relativists of our time could actually play a sinister role
if they permitted the “imaginative” to loosen our contact with the
objective world. For in the absence of rational objective standards
of behavior, imagination may be as demonic as it may be
liberatory when such standards exist; hence the need for informed
spontaneity — and an *informed* imagination. The exhilarating,
events of May-June 1968, with the cry “Imagination to Power!”
were followed a few years later by a surge in the popularity of
nihilistic postmodernism and poststructuralism in the academy,
an unsavory metaphysics of “desire,” and an apolitical call for
“imagination” nourished by a yearning for “self-realization.”
More than ever, I would insist, we must invert Nietzsche’s dictum
All facts are interpretations” and demand that all interpretations
be rooted in objectivity. We must seek out broader interpretations
of socialism than those that cast socialist ideals as a science and
strangled its movements in authoritarian institutions. At a time
when we teeter between Civilization and barbarism, the current
apostles of irrationality in all their varied forms are the chthonic
demons of a dark world who have come to life not to explicate
humanity’s problems but to effect a dispiriting denial of the role
of rationality in History and human affairs. My disquiet today lies
not in the absence of scientific “guarantees” that a libertarian
socialist society will appear — one that, at my age, it will never be
my privilege to see — but in *whether it will even he fought for* in so
decadent and desperate a period.
— February 15,1994
[77] Moreover, despite this tendency to bifurcate objectivity and subjectivity,
the two do not exclude each other. There is always a subjective dimension
to objectivity, but it is precisely the *relationship* between the two that requires explication.
[78] Moral relativism has recently been the breeding ground of a purely functional or instrumental form of rationality, which in my view is one of the
greatest impediments to serious social analysis and a meaningful ethics.
“Subjective reason,” to use Max Horkheimer’s phrase from
*The Eclipse of Reason*,
on which a relativistic approach rests, has been one of the major
afflictions of Anglo-American thinking, not merely within the academy
but within the general public.
[79] Predicated as their self-realization is in their own potentialities, human
beings *nevertheless cannot do as they please*, despite the assertions of
“beautiful souls,” to use Hegel’s phrase, who live in an aerie of personal
liberation and self-contained “autonomy.” Here, Marx was a good deal
ahead of today’s individualistic anarchists who have a bad habit of disrupting serious attempts at organization and theoretical inquiry with
simplistic cries of “Freedom now!”
[80] Nothing is easier, more mystifying, and more smug these days than to advance sweeping, ahistorical generalizations about figures like Hegel,
Marx, and Lenin. It is evidence of the ugly intellectual degradation of our
time that people who should know better make them so flippantly. One
might as well claim that Stalin’s totalitarianism had its roots in
Machiavelli’s so-called “Atlantic Republican Tradition” since the latter
was the author of *The Prince*; or in Plato, as Karl Popper so notoriously
did. Yet Hegel would undoubtedly have resolutely opposed Marx’s view
of the dialectic; Marx might very well have disowned Lenin, as the Marxist Rosa Luxemburg and the council communists Gorter and Pannekoek
did; and Stalin would certainly have imprisoned Lenin, as Lenin’s
widow bitterly reproached Trotsky in 1925, after the former Red Army
commander belatedly began to attack Stalin.
[81] Many of these former Marxists (particularly “New Left” students and
their professors) polluted the sixties with their pet dogmas, only to “grow
up” after they had “had their fun” (to rephrase a cynical expression of
many Parisian veterans of 1968) and are now polluting the nineties with
skepticism, nihilism, and subjectivism. The most serious obstacles to the
development of an authentic New Left today are the Alain Touraines,
Andr£ Gorzes, and Michael Walzers who have rallied variously to
“market socialism,” “minimal statism,” or pluralized concepts of justice
and freedom that are perfectly compatible with modern capitalism. The
worst fate that an idea can meet is to be kept artificially alive, long after it
has died historically, in the form of graduate courses at the New School
for Social Research in New York City.
[82] It is easy, when criticizing scientism as an ideology, to forget the role that
the natural *sciences* themselves played in subverting beliefs in witchcraft
and superstition, and in fostering a secular and naturalistic approach to
reality. I would like to think that we no longer believe in Dracula, or in
the power of the crucifix to fend off vampires, or in the occult power of
women to communicate with demons — or do we?
[83] See my “Introduction: A Philosophical Naturalism,” elsewhere in this
book.
[84] Indeed, there may be a “logic to events,” but it would be the logic of conventional reason, based on mere cause-and-effect and the principle of
identity, *A equals A*, not dialectical reason.
[85] See James Miller, *The Passion of Michel Foucault* (New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1993).
[86] See my forthcoming book *Re-Enchanting Humanity* (London: Cassell, 1995),
for a more detailed discussion of these issues.
[87] Ironically, it even vitiates the meaning of *social* anarchism as an ethical
socialism.
[88] I find no solace in the notion that preliterate peoples “enjoyed” an “affluent society,” as Marshall Sahlins would have it. Their lives were all too
often short, their cultures burdened by superstition and bereft of a syllabic system of writing, and they normally were at war with each other, to
cite only their major afflictions, pastoral New Age images of their lives to
the contrary.
[89] Indeed, even nominalistic historians who see History as a series of accidents often tacitly presuppose the existence of the “nonaccidental” (perhaps even the *rational*) in a social development.
[90] See chapter 11 of my *The Ecology of Freedom* (1982; reprinted by Montreal:
Black Rose Books, 1992).
[91] I find no view more one-sided and noxious than Theodor Adorno’s dictum, “No universal history leads from savagery to humanitarianism, but
there is one leading from the slingshot to the megaton bomb.” This inflated, less than thought-out pronouncement, taken together with
Adorno’s commitment to a negativity that rejected sublation (*Aufhebung*),
or social and ideological advances, was a step toward nihilism, indeed, an
ugly demonization of humanity, that belied his affirmations of reason.
See *Negative Dialectics*, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York: Seabury Press
1973), p. 320.
[92] I deliberately eschew the words *Totality* and *Spirit* to preclude any such suggestion.
[93] The name of another chapter in *The Ecology of Freedom*.
[94] G.W.F. Hegel, “Reason as Lawgiver,” in *Phenomenology of Spirit*, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), pp. 252–56.
[95] Hegel for all his entanglements with the notion of *Giest* or “Spirit” and
despite his conception of a predetermined “Absolute,” at least had the good sense to distinguish the self-development of nonhuman life-forms, for instance, from the self-development of humanity or, for that matter, society. See G.W.F. Hegel, “Introduction,” *Lectures on the History of Philosophy*, vol. 1, trans. E. S. Haldane and Frances H. Simson (1892; London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, and New York: The Humanities Press,
1955, 1968), pp. 22–23.
[96] Present-day cosmology and biophysics, however, are coming up against
phenomena whose explanation requires the flexible concepts of development advanced by dialectical naturalism.
[97] Karl Marx, “Toward a Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Law: Introduction,” *Writings of the Young Marx on Philosophy and Society*, trans. Lloyd D. Easton and Kurt H. Guddat (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday and Co., 1967) p. 259.
[98] W. T. Stace’s *Critical History of Greek Philosophy*, for example, shows how a
series of ancient Greek thinkers rounded out increasingly full but still one-sided views to produce the most advanced dialectical philosophy of their time, particularly that of Aristotle. Certainly the development of insight into the dialectical nature of reality did not end with the Greeks. Nor will it end with thinkers in our time, any more than science ended in the nineteenth century, when so many physicists thought little more could be added to complete Newtonian physics. In his history of philosophy, Hegel pointed out not only different *degrees* of dialectical reason, which approximated different degrees of truth (which in no way means that he was a “relativist”), but different *kinds* of rationality — “Understanding” or *Verstand*, of the commonsensical kind, and “Reason” or *Vernunft*, of the dialectical kind.
[99] Recently, dialectical naturalism has been criticized for committing the
“epistemological fallacy,” in which a priori concepts become their own conditions of validity, rendering dialectics as such a self-validating system. This, as if dialectic naturalism were not structured around the *reality* of potentiality and were purely an a priori speculative form of reason. Yet these critics themselves usually use the kind of logic that employs the most a priori, indeed tautological of all concepts, the principle of identity, *A equals A*, in preference to dialectical reason.
[100] This view is not new for me. In *The Ecology of Freedom*, completed in 1980
and published in 1982, I was at pains to indicate that “the *Dialectic of Enlightenment* is actually no dialectic at all — at least not in its attempt to explain the negation of reason through its own self-development” (p. 272).
My respect for the Frankfurt School rested largely on its insightful critique of positivism, which was the dominant philosophical fad in
American universities and social theory (so-called “sociology”) in the
1940s and 1950s, and on its various insights into Hegelian philosophy.
Today, these valuable contributions are far outweighed by the ease with
which the Frankfurt School’s work has fostered postmodern views in the
United States and Germany and by the extent to which its products,
especially Adorno’s writings, have become academic commodities.
[101] Nor does a verbal paradox that contrasts seemingly related but opposing
ideas, or colorful expressions of alterity, constitute a dialectic in the sense
in which I have discussed it here, however much it seems to resemble formulations in Hegel and the best of Marx. Adorno’s provocative endeavors of this kind often turn out to be little more than that — provocations.
[102] Presented by the IKD’s Auslands Kommitee (Committee Abroad), this
huge document long predated *Socialisme ou Barbarie*. The ideas that it ad
vanced, however, are moot today. Extrapolating Hitler’s seeming war
aims of the early 1940s — to reduce industrialized Western European
countries to mere satellites of German capital and to agrarianize and
depopulate the East — to the world at large, this theory of imperialism
(and barbarism) argued that deindustrialization would be exported to
undeveloped countries, and not, as old Marxist theories of imperialism
had assumed in the prewar period, capital.
[103] Nor did we, by the late 1940s, regard the workers’ movement — indeed,
“workers’ councils” or “workers’ control of industry” — as revolutionary,
especially with the sequelae of the great strike movements of the late
1940s, which directly affected my own life as a worker.
[104] The notion of an “instinct for freedom,” touted by many radical theorists,
is a sheer oxymoron. The compelling, indeed necessitarian character of
instinct makes it the very antithesis of freedom, whose liberating dimensions are grounded in choice and self-consciousness.